A SPECIAL ISSUE DEVOTED TO AUTOPOIESIS – CYBERNETICS FORURM (1981)

autopoiesis1

Reproduced from: http://www.univie.ac.at/aoc/asc/Periodica/X_2_3_1981.pdf


IN THIS ISSUE:

Foreword by the Special-Issues Editor, Klaus Krippendorff

Autopoiesis Today, Milan Zeleny

Autopoiesis: The Organization of Living Systems, Its Characterization and a Model, F.G. Varela, H.R. Maturana and A. Uribe

The Organization of the Living: A Theory of the Living Organization, Humberto R. Maturana

Self-Organization of Living Systems: A Formal Model of AutopoiesisMilan Zeleny

About the Authors

© 1981 American Society for Cybernetics


Foreword by the Special-Issues Editor

With this issue, Cybernetics Forum assumes a new responsibility. Rather than publishing original articles exclusively, an effort will be made to bring together and to organize cybernetic contributions to knowledge that are scattered throughout numerous and often hard-to­ find journals. We recognize that the emphasis on the “one cycle” mass dissemination of newly written articles, which is built into the tradition of journalism, sold to readers as a value and favored by copyright laws, may not promote quality. In contrast, we believe that the aim of furthering cybernetic insights might be better served by recycling articles from time to time whose ideas are prevented from bearing fruit because they ap­pear in obscure journals, by providing access to relevant literature through the publication of selected bibliographies, and by publishing overviews of par­ticular areas of research and theoretical development.

Individually, these issues of Cybernetics Forum might be used as mini-textbooks in classes on cybernetics, systems theory and as reference works in disciplines in which such ideas are applied. Collectively they serve to organize and further develop ideas, to define important issues, and to outline fruitful avenues for research. We also hope that these issues will provide the reader with the stepping stones for intellectual growth.

The issue before us is on autopoiesis. The idea is barely a decade old, has emerged in various intellectual domains, especially in biology, and is now in the pro­cess of becoming a new paradigm. It promises pro­foundly new insights in the social sciences, has tremen­dous philosophical implications, and will change our perspective on our worldview and on ourselves. Other topics being considered for future issues are self­-organization, evolution, and management.

Klaus Krippendorff


Autopoiesis Today

Milan Zeleny

The Joseph A. Martino Graduate School of Business Administration
Fordham University at Lincoln Center
New York, NY 10023

Introduction

Most biological and social systems are relatively in­variant manifestations of internal material changes evoked by processes of self-production. For example, the entire macromolecular population of components of a biological cell is renewed about 104 times during its life time. Yet, throughout this staggering turnover of matter, the cell maintains its distinctiveness, cohesiveness and relative autonomy. The maintenance of organizational unity and wholeness, under conditions of continuous or periodic dissassembly and rebuilding, creation and decimation, or production and consump­tion of the components of this unity is called autopoiesis.

The biological cell is not the only form of reality that displays this capability. All living systems are autopoietic in this sense. The organization of some social forms (ant colonies, human groupings, large cities, ideologies) is also primarily determined from within, through the interaction of their continuously replaced components, rather than from the outside through feedback from their environment. Even the organization of the central nervous system is to a large extent spontaneous (“automatic”), or indigenous and in­dependent of sensory feedback. The environment of liv­ing systems may perturb or modify their internal processes, and it may affect their components, but it can­ not fully explain their organization.

The input-output paradigm of the old (Wienerian) cybernetics provides for the description of systems as externally driven “black boxes” and this is adequate for understanding mechanical devices and systems of in­terest to engineering. But the application of this paradigm to living and social systems has been intellec­tually dissatisfying, misleading, and inhibitive of the recognition of those organizational features that make such systems living or social.

The interest in autopoietic organization requires no justification. The paradigm provides new insights into old phenomena and has profound implications for biology and the social sciences. We learn that phenomena of self-organization, reproduction, heredity, evolution and even learning are not primary processes but derived manifestations of autopoiesis. We begin to understand that DNA does not simply order a chaotic mass but that it interacts with self-ordered cells and large assemblies. It becomes more and more transparent why, for millions of years, species have re­tained their defining characteristics, the best explana­tion of which lies in their internal processes. We start to comprehend the resilience and adaptability of social systems, their spontaneous and persisting self­-production and material renewal, and their unyielding to social engineering manipulations. Autonomy, one of the most important properties of autopoietic organizations, has become a politically important value for the in­dividual as well as for various levels of social organizations.

Because of its paradigmatically different nature, autopoiesis cannot be easily compared with the tradi­tional input-output control approach. It is based on dif­ferent premises and presuppositions and it offers a dif­ferent view of reality. Only experience will tell us how powerful the autopoietic viewpoint is; the time required to reach such a resolution is bound to be substantial. Even if ultimately abandoned in favor of other ap­proaches, the alternative paradigms can only benefit from the challenging encounters with autopoiesis. Our view of the world, especially of living beings and social systems, can certainly never go back to what it was before the processes of autopoiesis became recognizable and penetrable.

The Papers

This issue of Cybernetics Forum introduces the reader to the idea of autopoiesis through the three key articles. These have appeared in rather different jour­nals but still can be considered to have ignited exciting developments whose ends are not yet in sight. The three articles are mostly self-explanatory; they are presented in the chronological order of their original published ap­pearance. The reader is encouraged to proceed directly with the papers and then return to the following over­view, which is intended to provide additional informa­tion.

The first paper, by Varela, Maturana and Uribe, represents the original exposition of autopoiesis as it appeared in Biosystems in 1974. It contains many in­troductory definitions and formulations of autopoiesis, reports some computational experience with a simula­tion model of autopoiesis, and provides a verbal description of the model. In the next article, published in the Journal of Man-Machine Studies in 1975, Maturana reveals the philosophical richness of autopoiesis through his discussion of the nervous system, concepts of structural coupling, ontogeny and evolution, and presents some bold excursions into the linguistic do­main. The third article appeared in General Systems in 1977. It contains a formal model of autopoiesis, exten­sive results (autopoietic rhythms, cellular division, mor­phology controls, etc.), as well as the initial notions of social autopoiesis.

Autopoiesis and Related Research

Of course, autopoiesis is not the only approach employed in the study of holistically emerging, self­-organizing, and spontaneously generated phenomena. Order by fluctuation, underlying the emergence and evolution of dissipative structures, is now being studied via non-equilibrium thermodynamics (see for example Nicolis and Prigogine, 1977). Theories of self-organizing hypercycles of catalytic synthesis of complex nucleic acids and proteins are still being advanced by Eigen and Schuster (1979). There is even a renewed interest in the rules of conduct and spontaneous social orders of van Hayek (1967). But autopoiesis, and its more general no­tion of organizational closure, appear capable of ad­dressing all of the above phenomenological domains.

Kenneth E. Boulding (1981) reacted to his own encounter with autopoiesis by observing that its pioneers, like Columbus’ three boats, probably thought they were heading for the Indies, that mysterious, still largely unknown, though spicy realm of human knowledge that studies the overwhelmingly mysterious and complex phenomenon of life. What they may well have sighted is a whole new continent, which no Amerigo has yet named, but the hazy outlines of which are now visible to the early explorers. This is nothing less than the study of the whole developmental process of the universe, that is, the general theory of evolution.

Boulding’s vision seems to reflect that research scat­tered over various domains is slowly forming a new system of interlocking ideas which crosses disciplinary boundaries. The bibliography presented here is intend­ed to allow the interested reader to recapture this ex­citement for himself and to develop his own perspective for the process. To broaden this context of understand­ing a few related works must be highlighted.

The recent papers by Goguen and Varela (1979) and by Faucheux and Makridakis (1979), go a long way towards presenting and explaining the control/autonomy dilem­ma of choice. New extensions as well as critical evalua­tions of autopoiesis are published in Autopoiesis: A Theory of Living Organization. Challenging applications, ranging from molecular biology to socio-economic systems, are collected to Autopoiesis, Dissipative Structures, and Spontaneous Social Orders. The original monograph of Maturana and Varela from 1973 has finally been published in English as Autopoiesis and Cognition. There is a renewed interest in exploring the historical roots of cybernetics and general systems theories. Several “paradigms lost” are being resur­rected, see for example Zeleny (1979), and new histories of these fields are likely to be written. Stafford Beer’s soul-searching “Preface to Autopoietic Systems” (1980) should not be missed. Paul A. Weiss, who has used the systems approach in biology since 1925, and whose writings are dominated by autopoietic thinking, received the National Medal of Science in 1980. There is even some obvious fascination with the metaphoric beauty of the term “autopoiesis,” as for example in the recent book by the late Erich Jantsch (1980).

Autopoiesis then, to paraphrase Boulding, is truly an idea whose time has come.

Bibliography of Autopoiesis

The following is a rather short selection of only those works which deal with autopoiesis as their main focus of attention. A large number of writings either referring to autopoiesis or briefly commenting upon it were not included; the reader can trace them quite easily from the references provided within the works listed here:

Books and monographs

  1. Maturana, H.R., and F.J. Varela: De Maquinas y Seros Vivos, Editorial Universitaria, Santiago, Chile, 1973. English translation: Autopoietic Systems, BCL Report 9.4, Biological Computer Laboratory, University of Illinois, Urbana, 1975.
  2. Maturana, H.R., and F.J. Varela: Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living, Boston ‘ Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 42, Reidel Publishing  Co., Boston, 1980.
  3. Varela, F.J.: Principles of Biological Autonomy, General Systems Research Series, Vol. 2, Elsevier North Holland, New York,
  4. Zeleny,  (ed.): Autopoiesis:  A Theory  of  Living Organization, General Systems Research Series, Vol. 3, Elsevier North Holland, New York,  1981.
  5. Zeleny, (ed.): Autopoiesis, Dissipative Struc­tures, and Spontaneous Social Orders, AAAS Selected Symposium 55, Westview Press, Boulder, Colo., 1980.

Articles

Andrew,  A.M.:   “Autopoiesis and Self-Organization,” Journal of Cybernetics, vol. 9, no. 4, 1979, pp. 359-368.

Andrew,  A.M.:  “Autopoiesis-Allopoiesis  Interplay,”  in [4], pp. 157-166.

Beer, S.: “Preface to Autopoietic Systems,”  in  [1],  pp. 1-16, and [2], pp. 1-8.

Boulding, K.E.: “Foreword,” in [5], pp. xvi-xxi.

Boulding, K.E.: “Foreword,” in [4], pp. xi-xiii.

Faucheux, C., and S. Makridakis: “Automation or Autonomy in Organizational Design,” International Journal of General Systems, vol. 5, no. 4, 1979, pp. 213-220.

Gaines,  B.:  “Autopoiesis-Some Questions,”   in   [4], pp. 145-154.

Guiloff,  G.:  “Autopoiesis and Neobiogenesis,” in [4], pp. 118-125.

Jantsch, E.: “The Unifying Paradigm Behind Auto­ poiesis, Dissipative Structures, Hyper- and Ultra­ cycles,” in [5], pp. 81-87.

Jantsch, E.: “Autopoiesis: A Central Aspect of Dissipa­tive Self-Organization,” in [4], pp. 65-88.

Locker, A.: “Meta-Theoretical Presuppositions for Autopoiesis (Self-Reference and Autopoiesis),” in [4], pp. 211-233.

Maturana, H.R.: “The Organization of the living: A Theory of the Living Organization,” International Journal of Man-Machine Studies, vol. 7, no. 3, 1975, 313-333.

Maturana, H.R.: “Autopoiesis,” in (4], pp. 21-33.

Maturana, H.R.: “Autopoiesis: Reproduction, Heredity and Evolution,” in [5], pp. 45-79.

Maturana, H.R., and F.J. Varela: “Introductory Remarks,” in [4], pp. 18-19.

Morin, E.: “Self and Autos,” in [4], pp. 128-137.

Uribe, R.B.: “Modeling Autopoiesis,” in [4], pp. 51-61.

Varela, F.J.: “Describing  the logic of the living,” in [4], pp. 34-48.

Varela, F.J., and J.A. Goguen: “The Arithmetic of Closure,” Journal of Cybernetics, vol. 8, no. 3-4, 1978, pp. 291-324.

Varela, F.G., H.R. Maturana, and R.B. Uribe: “Auto­poiesis: The Organization of living Systems, Its Characterization and a Model,” BioSystems, vol. 5, no. 4, 1974, pp. 187-196.

Zeleny, M.: “Organization as an Organism,” Proceed­ings of the 1977 Annual Meeting of the Society for General Systems Research, SGSR, Washington, D.C., 1977, pp. 262-270.

Zeleny, M.: “Self-Organization of living Systems: A Formal Model of Autopoiesis,” International Journal of General Systems, vol. 4, no. 1, 1977, pp. 13-28.

Zeleny, M.: ” APL-AUTOPOIESIS: Experiments in Self­ Organization of Complexity,” in R.  Trappl,  et  al., (eds.), Progress in Cybernetics and Systems  Re· search, Vol. Ill, Hemisphere Publishing Corp., Wash­ington, D.C., 1978, pp. 65-84.

Zeleny, M.: “Autopoiesis: A Paradigm Lost?,” in [5], pp. 3-43.

Zeleny, M.: “What Is Autopoiesis?,” in [4], pp. 4-17.

Zeleny, M.: “Autogenesis: On the Self-Organization of life,” in[4], pp. 91-11 5.

Zeleny, M., and N.A. Pierre: “Simulation Models of Auto­ poietic Systems,” Proceedings of the 1975 Computer Simulation Conference, Simulation Councils, La Jolla, Calif., 1975, pp. 831-842.

Zeleny, M., and N.A. Pierre: “Simulation of Self-Renew­ing Systems,” in E. Jantsch and C.H. Waddington (eds.)., Evolution and Consciousness, Addison­ Wesley, Reading, Mass., 1976, pp. 150-165.

Computer Modeling of Autopoiesis

There is now available an interactive modeling package, entitled APL-Autopoiesis, suitable for research experimentation with self-organizing systems as well as for game, educational and instructional ap­ plications. It is written in the APL language and is fully equipped with special purpose subprograms. The user is allowed to create and implement his own programs and variations through an unlocked APL control pro­gram AUTO.

The system is available in one APL workspace (the minimum workspace size is 64K) on an 800 bpi, 9-track non-labeled magnetic tape. The tape is created by the IBM utility DQCEUOO, and has the external label AUTOV2. The blocksize is 4000 bytes.

APL-Autopoiesis features print control, statistics plot control, multiple catalysts, production control, link movement control, time limit control, neighborhood control, interaction control, enclosure check control, moving catalysts, print timing control, etc., allowing the user to model desired situations or play interactive com­petitive games.

User’s Manual and leasing/buying information is available from:

COMPUTING AND SYSTEMS CONSULTANTS, Inc.
P.O. Box 1551
Binghamton, NY 13902
U.S.A.

The best way to appreciate and understand the dynamics and the continuous structural transforma­tions of an autopoietic system is through a transcription of the computer output on a video-tape. Autopoiesis can then be observed as a continuous “film” rather than a series of slides. This is now available on SONY video­ cassette, U-matic, KC-30, in five colors and accompanied by sound. The experience of viewing the emergence and functioning of an autopoietic system through this medium is quite fascinating. It also further underlines the vast potential role the computers can play in the study of living  systems.

Autopoiesis Interest Group

The growing number of scientists interested in general aspects of self-organization, autopoiesis, and order through fluctuation has prompted the initiation of “the list” of such persons from a large variety of disciplines.

The purpose of this grouping is to exchange informa­tion, maintain and update the relevant literature, and en­courage more vigorous discussion across disciplines and across paradigms.

Further information is avail able from:

Dr. G.J. Dalenoort
Institute of Experimental Psychology University of Groningen
P.O. Box 14 9750 AA Haren The Netherlands

References

Beer, S.: “Preface to Autopoietic Systems,” in H.R. Maturana and F.J. Varela, Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 42, D. Reidel Publishing Co., Boston, 1980, pp. 1-8.

Boulding, K.E.: “Foreword,” in M. Zeleny (ed.), Auto­poiesis: A Theory of the Living Organization, General Systems Research Series, Vol. 3, Elsevier North Holland, New York, 1980, pp. xi-xiii.

Faucheux, C., and S. Makridakis: “Automation or Autonomy in Organizational Design,” International Journal of General  Systems,  vols. 5, no. 4,  1979, pp. 213-220.

Eigen, M., and P. Schuster: The Hypercycle: A Principle of Natural Self-Organization, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1979.

Goguen, J.A., and F.J. Varela: “Systems and Distinc­tions; Duality and Complementarity,” International Journal of General  Systems, vol. 5, no. 1, 1979, pp. 31-43.

Jantsch, E.: The Self-Organizing Universe, Pergamon Press, New York, 1980.

Nicolis, G., and I. Prigogine: Self-Organization in Non­ Equilibrium  Systems, John Wiley, New York, 1977.

Von Hayek, F.A.: Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, Chapter on “Notes on the Evolution of Systems of Rules of Conduct,” Clarion Books, Simon & Schuster, New York,  1967.

Zeleny, M.: “Cybernetics and General  Systems-A Unitary Science?,” Kybernetes, vol. 8, no. 1, 1979, pp. 17-23.

Zeleny, M.: “Special Book Reviews: B. Trentowski, Stosunek Filozofii do Cybernetyki czyli Sztuki Rzadzenia Narodem; A.A. Bogdanov, Tektologia: Vseobhschaya Organizatsionnaya Nauka; J. Ch. Smuts, Holism and Evolution; S. Leduc, The Mechanism of Life,” International Journal of General Systems, vol. 5, no. 1, 1979, pp. 63-71.


Autopoiesis:
The Organization of Living Systems, Its  Characterization and a Model

F.G. Varela, H.R. Maturana and R. Uribe

Facultad de Ciencias e Departamento de Electricidad, University of Chile, Santiago, Chile

[The article first appeared in BioSystems, Vol. 5, 1974, published  by Elsevier North-Holland Biomedical Press R.V. We appreciate the permission of the publisher to re­typeset the article.]

We formulate the organization of living organisms through the characterization of the class of autopoietic systems to which living things belong. This general characterization is seen at work in a computer simulated model of a minimal case satisfying the conditions for autopoietic organization.

1.  Introduction

Notwithstanding their diversity, all living systems must share a common organization which we implicitly recognize by calling  them “living”. At present there is no formulation of this organization, mainly because the great developments of molecular, genetic and evolu­tionary notions in contemporary biology have led to the overemphasis of isolated components, e.g. to consider reproduction as a necessary feature of the living organization and, hence, not to ask about the organiza­tion which makes a living system a whole, autonomous unity that is alive regardless of whether it reproduces or not. As a result, processes that are history dependent (evolution, ontogenesis) and history independent (individual organization) have been confused in the at­tempt to provide a single mechanistic explanation for phenomena which, although related, are fundamentally distinct.

We assert that reproduction and evolution are not constitutive features of the living organization and that the properties of a unity cannot be accounted for only through accounting for the properties of its com­ponents. In contrast, we claim that the living organiza­tion can only be characterized unambiguously by speci­fying the network of interactions of components which constitute a living system as a whole, that is, as a “unity”. We also claim that all biological phenomenology, in­cluding reproduction and evolution, is secondary to the establishment of this unitary organization. Thus, in­stead of asking “What are the necessary properties of the components that make a living system possible?” we ask “What is the necessary and sufficient organiza­tion for a given system to be a living unity?” In other words, instead of asking what makes a living system reproduce, we ask what is the organization reproduced when a living system gives origin to another living unity? In what follows we shall  specify this organization.

2.  Organization

Every unity can be treated either as an unanalyzable whole endowed with constitutive properties which define it as a unity, or else as a complex system that is realized as a unity through its components and their mutual relations. If the latter is the case, a complex system is defined as a unity by the relations between its components which realize the system as a whole, and its properties as a unity are determined by the way this unity is defined, and not by particular properties of its components. It is these relations which define a com­plex system as a unity and constitute its organization. Accordingly, the same organization may be realized in different systems with different kinds of components as long as these components have the properties which realize the required relations. It is obvious that with respect to their organization such systems are members of the same class, even though with respect to the nature of their components they may be distinct.

3.  Autopoietic Organization

It is apparent that we may define classes of systems (classes of unities) whose organization is specifiable in terms of spatial relations between components. This is the case of crystals, different kinds of which are defined only by different matrices of spatial relations. It is also apparent that one may define other classes of systems whose organization is specifiable only in terms of rela­tions between processes generated by the interactions of components, and not by spatial relations between these components. Such is the case of mechanistic systems in general, different kinds of (relations) of processes. In particular this is the case of living systems whose organization as a subclass of mechanistic systems we wish to specify.

The autopoietic organization is defined as a unity by a network of productions of components which (i) par­ticipate recursively in the same network of productions of components which produced these components, and (ii) realize the network of productions as a unity in the space in which the components exist. Consider for ex­ample the case of a cell: it is a network of chemical reac­tions which produce molecules such that (i) through their interactions generate and participate recursively in the same network of reactions which produced them, and (ii) realize the cell as a material unity. Thus the cell as a physical unity, topographically and operationally separable from the background, remains as such only insofar as th!s organization is continuously realized under permanent turnover of matter, regardless of its changes in form and specificity of its constitutive chemical reactions.

4.  Autopoiesis and Allopoiesis

The class of systems that exhibit the autopoietic organization, we shall call autopoietic systems.

Autonomy is the distinctive phenomenology resulting from an autopoietic organization: the realization of the autopoietic organization is the product of its operation. As long as an autopoietic system exists, its organiza­tion is invariant; if the network of productions of com­ponents which define the organization is disrupted, the unity disintegrates. Thus an autopoietic system has a domain in which it can compensate for perturbations through the realization of its autopoiesis, and in this do­main it remains a unity.

In contradistinction, mechanistic systems whose organization is such that they do not produce the com­ponents and processes which realize them as unities and, hence, mechanistic systems in which the product of their operation is different from themselves, we call allopoietic. The actual realization of these systems, therefore, is determined by processes which do not enter in their organization. For example, although the ribosome itself is partially composed of components produced by ribosomes, as a unity it is produced by pro­cesses other than those which constitute its operation. Allopoietic systems are by constitution non­-autonomous insofar as their realization and per­manence as unities is not related to their operation.

5.  Autopoiesis: The Living Organization

The biological evidence available today clearly shows that living systems belong to the class of autopoietic systems. To prove that the autopoietic organization is the living organization, it is then sufficient to  show, on  the other hand, that an autopoietic system is a living system. This has been done by showing that for a system to have the phenomenology of a living system it suffices that its organization be autopoietic (Maturana and Varela, 19-73).

Presently, however, it should be noticed that in this characterization, reproduction does not enter as a re­quisite feature of the living organization. In fact, for reproduction to take place there must be a unity to be reproduced: the establishment of the unity is logically and operationally antecedent to its reproduction. In liv­ing systems the organization reproduced is the autopoietic organization, and reproduction takes place in the process of autopoiesis; that is, the new unity arises in the realization of the autopoiesis of the old one. Reproduction in a living system is a process of divi­sion which consists, in principle, of a process of fragmentation of an autopoietic unity with distributed autopoiesis such that the cleavage separates fragments that carry the same autopoietic network of production of components that defined the original unity. Yet, although self-reproduction is not a requisite feature of the living organization, its occurrence in living systems as we know them is a necessary condition for the generation of a historical network of successively generated, not necessarily identical, autopoietic unities, that is, for evolution.

6.  A Minimal Case: The Model

We wish to present a simple embodiment of the autopoietic organization. This model is significant in two respects: on the one hand, it permits the observa­tion of the autopoietic organization at work in a system simpler than any known living system, as well as its spontaneous generation from components; on the other hand, it may permit the development of formal tools for the analysis and synthesis of autopoietic systems.

The model consists of a two-dimensional universe where numerous  elements (“substrate”), and a few  (“catalysts”) move randomly in the spaces of  a quadratic grid. These elements are endowed with specific properties which determine interactions that may result in the production of other elements  (“links”) with properties of their own and also capable of interactions (“bonding”). Let the interactions and transformations be as follows:

Interaction [1) between the catalyst  and two substrate elements 2  is responsible for the composi­tion of an unbonded link . These links may be bonded through Interaction [2) which concatenates these bond­ed links to unbranched chains of . A chain so pro­duced may close upon itself, forming an enclosure which we assume to be penetrable by the ‘s, but not  for . Disintegration (Interaction [31)] is assumed to be independent of the state of links , i.e., whether they are free or bound, and can be viewed either as a spontaneous decay or as a result of a collision with a substrate element .

In order to visualize the dynamics of the system, we show two sequences (Figures 1 and 2) of successive stages of transformation as they were obtained from the print-out of a computer simulation of this system.*

[*Details of computation are given in the Appendix. To facilitate appreciation of the developments, Fig. 1 and 2 are drawn from the print-outs with change of symbols used in the computations.]

If an -chain closes on itself enclosing an element (Fig. 1), the ‘s produced within the enclosure by In­teraction (1) can replace in the chain, via [2], the elements that decay as a result of [3] (Fig. 2). In this manner, a unity is produced which constitutes a net­work of productions of components that generate and participate in the network of productions that produced these components by effectively realizing the network as a distinguishable entity in the universe where the elements exist. Within this universe these systems satisfy the autopoietic organization. In fact, element  and elements  produce  element  in an enclosure formed by a bidimensional chain of ‘s; as a result the ‘s produced in the enclosure replace the decaying ‘s of the boundary, so that the enclosure remains closed for  under continuous turnover of elements, and under recursive generation of the network of pro­ductions which thus remains invariant (Figs. 1 and 2). This unity cannot be described in geometric terms because it is not defined by the spatial relations of its components. If one stops all the processes of the system at a moment in which  is enclosed by the -chain, so that spatial relations between the com­ponents become fixed, one indeed has a system definable in terms of spatial relations, that is, a crystal, but not an autopoietic unity.

It should be apparent from this model that the pro­cesses generated by the properties of the components (Schema I) can be concatenated in a number of ways. The autopoietic organization is but one of them, yet it is the one that by definition implies the realization of a dynamic unity. The same components can generate other, allopoietic organizations; for example, a chain which Is defined as a sequence of ‘s, is clearly allopoietic since the production of the components that realize it as a unity do not enter into its definition as a unity. Thus, the autopoietic organization is neither represented nor embodied in Schema I, as in general no organization is represented or embodied in the proper­ ties that realize it. 

7.  Tessellation and Molecules

In the case described, as in a broad spectrum of other studies that can generically be called tessellation automata (von Neumann, 1966; Gardner, 1971), the start­ing point is a generalization of the physical situation. In fact, one defines a space where spatially distinguishable components interact, thus embodying the concatenation of processes which lead to events among the components. This is of course what happens to the molecular domain, where autopoiesis as we know it takes place. For the purpose of explaining and study­ing the notion of autopoiesis, however, one may take a more general view as we have done here, and revert to the tessellation domain where physical space is re­placed by any space (a two-dimensional one in the model), and molecules by entities endowed with some properties. The phenomenology is unchanged in all cases: the autonomous self-maintenance of a unity while its organization remains invariant in time.

It is apparent that in order to have autopoietic systems, the components cannot be simple in their pro­perties. In the present case we required that the com­ponents have specificity of interactions, forms of linkage, mobility and decay. None of these properties are dispensable for the formation of this autopoietic system. The necessary feature is the presence of a boundary which is produced by a dynamics such that the boundary creates the conditions required for this dynamics. These properties should provide clues to the kind of molecules we should look for in order to produce an autopoietic system in the molecular domain. We believe that the synthesis of molecular autopoiesis can be attempted at present, as suggested by studies like those on microspheres and liposomes (Fox, 1965; Bangham, 1968) when analyzed in the present framework. For example: a liposome whose membrane lipidic components are produced and/or modified by reactions that take place between its components, only under the conditions of concentration produced within the liposome membrane, would. constitute an autopoietic system. No experiments along these lines have been carried out, although they are potential keys for the origin of living systems.

8.  Summary

We shall summarize the basic notions that have been developed in this  paper:

A. There are mechanistic systems that are defined as unities by a particular organization which we call autopoietic. These systems are different from any other mechanistic system in that the product of their opera­tion as systems thus defined is necessarily always the system itself. If the network of processes that con­stitutes the autopoietic system is disrupted, the system disintegrates .

B. The phenomenology of an autopoietic system is the phenomenology of autonomy: all changes of state (internal relations) in the system that takes place without disintegration are changes in autopoiesis which perpetuate autopoiesis.

C. An autopoietic system arises spontaneously from the interaction of otherwise independent elements when these interactions constitute a spatially con­ tiguous network of productions which manifests itself as a unity in the space of its elements.

D. The properties of the components of an autopoietic system do not determine its properties as a unity. The properties of an autopoietic system (as is the case for every system) are determined by the constitu­tion of this unity, and are, in fact, the properties of the network created by, and creating, its components. Therefore, to ascribe a determinant value to any compo­nent, or to any of its properties, because they seem to be “essential”, is a semantic artifice. In other words, all the components, and the components’ properties, as well as the circumstances which permit their productive interactions, are necessary when they participate in the realization of an autopoietic network, and none is deter­minant of the constitution of the network or of its pro­perties as a unity.

9.  Key

The following is a six-point key for determining whether or not a given unity is autopoietic:

  1. Determine, through interactions, if the unity has identifiable boundaries. If the boundaries can be deter­mined, proceed to 2. If not, the entity is indescribable and we can say nothing.
  2. Determine if there are constitutive elements of the unity, that is, components of the unity. If these com­ponents can be described, proceed to 3. If not, the unity is an unanalyzable whole and therefore not an autopoietic system.
  3. Determine if the unity is a mechanistic system, that is, the component properties are capable of satisfy­ing certain relations that determine in the unity the interactions and transformations of these components. If this is the case, proceed to 4. If not, the unity is not an autopoietic system.
  4. Determine if the components that constitute the boundaries of the unity constitute these boundaries through preferential neighborhood relations and in­teractions between themselves, as determined by their properties in the space of their interactions. If this is not the case, you do not have an autopoietic unity because you are determining its boundaries, not the unity itself. If 4 is the case, however, proceed to 5.
  5. Determine if the components of the boundaries of the unity are produced by the interactions of the com­ponents of the unity, either by transformations of previously produced components, or by transformations and/or coupling of non-component elements that enter the unity through its boundary. If not, you do not have an autopoietic unity; if yes, proceed to 6.
  6. If all the other components of the unity are also produced by the interactions of its components as in 5, and if those which are not produced by the interactions of other components, you have an autopoietic unity in the space in which its components exist. If this is not the case and there are components in the unity not pro­duced by components of the unity as in 5, or if there are components of the unity which do not participate in the production of other components, you do not have an autopoietic unity.

Acknowledgement

The authors wish to express their gratitude to the members of the Biological Computer Laboratory of the University of Illinois, Urbana, particularly to Richard Howe, Heinz Von Foerster, Paul E. Weston and Kenneth Wilson, for their continuous encouragement, discussions, and help in clarifying and sharpening the presen­tation of our notions.

References

Bangham, D.D., 1968, Membrane models with phos­pholipids, Progr. Biophys. Mol. Biol., 18, 29.

Fox, S., 1965, A theory of macromolecular and cellular origins, Nature, 205, 328.

Gardner, M., 1971, On cellular automata, self-repro­duction, the Garden of Eden, and the game “life”, Sci. Amer., 224 (2), 112.

Maturana, H.R. and F.G. Varela, 1974, De maquinas y seros vivas, (Editorial Universitaria, Santiago).

von Neumann, J., 1966, The theory of self-reproducing automata, ed. A. Burks (University of Illinois Press, Urbana).

APPENDIX

Conventions

We shall use the following alphanumeric symbols to designate  the elements referred to earlier:

The algorithm has two principal phases concerned, respectively, with the motion of the components over the two dimensional array of positions, and with produc­tion and disintegration of the L components out of and back into the substrate S’s. The rules by which L com­ponents bond to form a boundary complete the algorithm.

The “space” is a rectangular array of points, in­dividually addressable by their row and column positions within the array. In its initial state this space con­ tains one or more catalyst molecules K with all remain­ ing positions containing substrate S.

In both the motion and production phases, it is necessary to make random selections among certain sets of positions neighboring the particular point in the space at which the algorithm is being applied. The numbering scheme of Figure 3 is then applied; with location O in the figure being identified with the point of application (of course, near the array boundaries, not all of the neigtibor locations identified in the figure will ac­tually be found).

Regarding motion, the components are ranked by in­creasing “mass” as S, L, K. The S’s may not displace any other species, and thus are only able to move into “holes” or empty spaces in the grid, though they can pass through a single thickness of bonded link BL’s to do so. On the other hand the L and K readily displace S’s, pushing them into adjacent holes, if these exist, or else exchanging positions with them, thus passing free­ly through the substrate S. The most massive, K, can similarly displace free L links. However, neither of these can pass through a bonded link segment, and are thus effectively contained by a closed membrane. Con­catenated L’s, forming bonded link segments, are sub­ject to no motions at all.

Regarding production, the initial state contains no bonded links at all; these appear only as the result of for­mation from  substrate S’s in the presence of the catalyst. This occurs whenever two adjacent neighbor­ing positions of a catalyst are occupied by S’s (e.g., 2 and 7, or 5 and 4 in Figure 3). Only one L is formed per time step, per catalyst, with multiple possibilities being resolved by randomchoice. Since two S’s are combined to form one L, each such production leaves a new hole in the space, into which S’s may diffuse.

The disintegration of L’s is applied as a uniform probability of disintegration per time step for each L whether bonded or free, which results in a proportionali­ty between failure rate and size of chain structure. The sharply limited rate of ” repair”, which depends upon random motion of S’s through the membrane, random production of new L’s and random motion to the repair site, makes the disintegration a very powerful controller of the maximum size for a viable boundary structure. A disintegration probability of less than about .01 per time step is required in order to achieve any viable structure at all (these must contain roughly ten L units at least to form a closed structure with any space inside).

Algorithm

  1. Motion, first step

1.1. Form a list of the coordinates of all holes hi

1.2. For each hi, make a random selection, ni, in the range 1 through 4, specifying a neighboring loca­tion.

1.3. For each hi in turn, where possible move occu­pant of selected neighboring location in hi.

1.31.  If the neighbor is a hole or lies outside the space, take no action.

1.32.  If the neighbor ni contains a bonded L, ex­amine the location n’i· If n’i contains an S, move this S to hi·

1.4. Bond any moved L, if  possible (Rules, 6).

  1. Motion, second step

2.1.  Form a list of the coordinates of free L’s, mi.

2.2.  For each mi, make a random selection, ni, in the range 1 through 4, specifying a neighboring  loca­tion.

2.3.  Where possible, move the L occupying the loca­tion mi into the specified neighboring location.

2.31.  If location specified by ni contains another Lor a K, then take no action.

2.32.  If location specified by ni contains an S, the S will be displaced.

2.321.  If there is a hole adjacent to the S, it will move into it. If more than one such hole, select randomly.

2.322.  If the S can be moved into a hole by passing through bonded links, as in step 1, then it will do so.

2.323.  If the S cannot be moved into a hole, it will ex­change locations with the moving L.

2.33. If the location specified by ni is a hole, then  L simply moves into it.

2.4.  Bond each moved L, if possible.

  1. Motion, third step

3.1.  Form a list of the coordinates of all K’s, ci.

3.2.  For each ci, make a random selection ni, in the range 1 through 4, specifying a neighboring loca­tion.

3.3.  Where possible, move the K into the selected neighboring location.

3.31.  If the location specified by ncontains a BL or another K, take no action.

3.32.  If the location specified by ni contains a free L, which may be displaced according to the rules of 2.3, then the L will be moved, and the K moved into its  place. (Bond the moved L, if possible).

3.33.  If the location specified by ni contains an S, then move the S by the rules of  2.32.

3.34.  If the location specified by ni contains a free L, not movable by rules 2.3, exchange the positions of the K and L. (Bond L if  possible).

3.35.  If the location specified by ni is a hole, the K moves into it.

  1. Production

4.1.  For each catalyst ci, form a list of the neighbor­ing positions nij, which are occupied by S’s.

4.11.  Delete from the list of nij all positions for which neither adjacent neighbor position appears in the list (i.e., “1” must be deleted from the list of nij‘s, if neither 5 nor 6 appears, and a “6” must be deleted if neither 1 nor 2  appears).

4.2. For each cwith a non-null list of nij choose randomly one of the nij let its value be pi, and at the corresponding location, replace  the S by  a free  L.

4.21.  If the list of nij contains only one which is adja­cent to pi, then remove the corresponding S.

4.22.  If the list of nij includes both locations adja­cent to pi, randomly select the S to  be removed.

4.3.  Bond each produced L, if possible.

  1. Disintegration

5.1.  For each L, bonded or unbonded, select a ran­dom real number, d, in the range (0,1).

5.1.1.  If d Pd (Pd an adjustable parameter of the algorithm), then remove the corresponding L, at­tempt to re-bond (Rules, 7).

5.12.  Otherwise proceed to next L.

  1. Bonding

This step must be given the coordinates of a free L.

6.1.  Form a list of the neighboring positions ni , which contains free L’s, and the neighboring posi­tions mi, which contain singly bonded L’s.

6.2.  Drop from the mi any which would result in a bond angle less than 90°. (Bond angle is determined as in Figure 4).

6.3.  If there are two or more of the mi, select two, form the corresponding bonds, and exit.

6.4.  If there is exactly one mi, form the correspond­ing bond.

6.41.  Remove from the nany which would now result in a bond angle of less than 90°.

6.42.  If there are no ni, exit.

6.43. Select one of the ni, form the bond, and exit.

6.5.  If there are no ni, exit.

6.6.  Select one of the ni, form the corresponding bond, and drop it from the list.

6.61.  If the ni list is non-null, execute steps 6.41 through 6.43.

6.62.  Exit.

  1. Rebond

7.1.  Form a list of all neighbor positions mi occupied by singly bonded L’s.

7.2.  Form a second list, pij, of pairs of the mi which can be bonded.

7.3.  If there are any pij choose a maximal subset and form the bonds. Remove the L’s involved from the list mi.

7.4.  Add to the bond mi any neighbor locations oc­cupied by free L’s.

7.5.  Execute steps 7.1 through 7.3, then exit.


The Organization of the Living:

A Theory of the Living Organization*

Humberto  R. Maturana

Facultad  de Ciencias, Universidad  de  Chile,

Santiago, Chile

(Received 2 October 1974)

[The article first appeared in International Journal of Man-Machine Studies, Vol. 7, 1975 published by Academic Press, Inc. (London) Ltd. We appreciate the permission of the publisher to re-typeset the article.


*An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Conference on Biologically Motivated Automata Theory, Maclean, U.S.A., 19-21 June 1974.]

The fundamental feature that characterizes living systems is autonomy, and any account of their organiza­tion as systems that can exist as individual unities must show what autonomy is as a phenomenon proper to them, and how it arises in their operation as such unities. Accordingly the following is proposed.

(1) That autonomy in living systems is a feature of self-production (autopoiesis}, and that a living system is properly characterized only as a network of processes of production of components that is continuously, and recursively, generated and realized as a concrete entity (unity) in the physical space, by the interactions of the same components that it produces as such a network. This organization I call the autopoietic organization, and any system that exhibits it is an autopoietic system in the space in which its components exist; in this sense living systems are autopoietic systems in the physical space.

(2) That the basic consequence of the autopoietic organization is that everything that takes place in an autopoietic system is subordinated to the realization of its autopoiesis, otherwise it disintegrates.

(3) That the fundamental  feature  that  characterizes the nervous system is that it is a closed network of in­teracting neurons in which every state of neuronal ac­tivity generates other states of neuronal activity. Since the nervous system is a component subsystem in an autopoietic unity, it operates by generating states of relative neuronal activity that participate in the realiza­tion of the autopoiesis of the organism which it integrates.

(4) That the autopoietic states that an organism adopts are determined by its structure (the structure of the nervous  system included), and that the structure of the organism (including its nervous system) is at any in­stant the result of its evolutionary and ontogenic struc­tural coupling with the medium in which it is autopoietic, obtained while the autopoiesis is realized.

(5) That language arises as phenomenon proper to liv­ing systems from the reciprocal structural coupling of at least two organisms with nervous systems, and that self-consciousness arises as an individual phenomenon from the recursive structural coupling of an organism with language with its own structure through recursive self-description.

Purpose

My purpose in this article is to present a theory of the organization of living systems as autonomous entities, and a theory of the organization of the nervous system as a closed network of interacting neurons structurally coupled to the living system to whose realization it con­tributes.

Antecedents

(a) There is no adequate theory of the organization of living systems as individual autonomous unities. There are only descriptions of some of their internal states and of their states of interaction as these appear pro­jected upon the domain of observation and purposeful design of the observer. Thus, reproduction, processing of information or internal hierarchical relations, are described as fundamental constitutive features of the living organization. Yet, at a closer scrutiny, none of these features appears to be exclusive, or definitory of living systems. In fact, reproduction is trivially non­-constitutive, even though it is necessary for evolution, because living systems are living systems, whether in reproduction or not, as long as they are “alive”. The no­tion of processing of information represents a way of description of the interactions and changes of state of a system, and as such it is applicable to any possible dynamic system. Finally, the possession of internal hierarchical relations is a feature that an observer can ascribe to any mechanistic system to which he assigns an initial and a final state in its sequential-state translations. The same applies to the nervous system. There is no adequate theory of the nervous system as a neuronal network embedded in an autonomous living unity; there are only descriptions of the state transitions of the ner­vous system viewed as an input-output system de­signed for the processing of environmental information. The result of this view is the treatment of the nervous system as an organ through which the organism becomes semantically coupled to its environment, as if the features of the description (semantic relations) were effective operative components in the changes of state of the organism.

(b) It is the aim of many scientists who work in automata theory to model the most unique phenomena generated by living systems such as autonomy, language and self-consciousness. Such an aim, however, cannot be achieved in the absence of a theory that shows the nature of these phenomena and how they arise in biological systems.

Preliminary Concepts

Observer. An observer is a human being, a person; so­meone who can make distinctions and specify that which he distinguishes as an entity (a something) dif­ferent from himself, and can do this with his own ac­tions and thoughts recursively, being always able to operate as if external to (distinct from) the cir­cumstances in which he finds himself. All the distinc­tions that we handle, conceptually or concretely, are made by us as observers: everything said is said by an observer to another observer.

Unity. A unity is an entity (concrete or conceptual) separated from a background by a concrete of conceptual operation of distinction. A unity may be treated as an unanalyzable whole endowed with constitutional properties,
or as a composite entity with properties as a unity that are specified by its organization and not by the properties of its components.

Interaction. Whenever two unities, specified by their properties and as a result of the interplay of these pro­perties, appear to modify their relative states in reference to the larger systems in which they are embedded, there is an interaction.

Space. Space is the domain of all the possible rela­tions and interactions of a collection of elements that the properties of these elements define.

Explanation. An explanation is always addressed by an observer to another observer. An explanation is an in­tended reproduction. A system is explained when the relations which define it as a unity are, either concep­tually or concretely, intentionally reproduced. A phenomenon is explained when the processes which generate it are, either conceptually or concretely, inten­tionally reproduced in a manner that shows that by their operation they generate the phenomenon to be explain­ed. It follows that there are two basic problems that must be solved in any explanation, namely: (a) the distinction and identification of the unity or phenomenon to be explained; and (b) the conceptual or concrete reproduction, either of the organization of the unity or of the mechanisms and processes that generate the phenomenon to be explained.

Organization. This word comes from the Greek term aoyavov (organon) that means instrument, and by mak­ing reference to the instrumental participation of the components in the constitution of the unity, it refers to the relations between components which define a system as a unity. So, in order to define a system as a unity it is necessary and sufficient to point to its organization. From the cognitive point of view, the organizations of a unity specifies the concept which defines the class of unities to which it belongs.

Structure. This word comes from the latin verb struere that means to build, and by making reference to the pro­cess of construction as well as to the components of a construct, it refers to the actual components and to the actual relations which these must satisfy in their par­ticipation in the constitution of a given unity. An observer may recognize a known system by identifying its components, but an unknown system cannot be defined by pointing to its structure.

Organization and structure, therefore, are not synonyms. The organization of a composite system con­stitutes it as a unity and determines its properties as such a unity, specifying a domain in which it may in­teract (and be treated) as an unanalyzable whole. The structure of a composite system determines the space in which it exists and can be perturbed, but not its pro­perties as a unity. An unanalyzable unity can be iden­tified by a concept, but it does not have an organization, nor does it have a structure, it only has properties as a fundamental element that exists in a space which these properties specify. It follows that two spatially separated composite unities may have the same organization but different structures and that a com­posite unity (system) remains the same only as long as its organization remains invariant: whenever the organization of a unity changes the unity changes, it becomes a different unity; whenever the structure of a unity changes without change in its organization, the unity remains the same and its identity stays unchang­ed. It also follows that when the organization of a unity is to be explained it is a mistake to reproduce its struc­ture, it is necessary and sufficient to reproduce its organization and, thus produce one of the kind;  yet, when a particular unity is to be reproduced, both its organization and its structure must be reproduced.

Furthermore, since a composite unity interacts through the properties of its components, and an unanalyzable one through its constitutive properties as a unity, all interactions between unities, including in­teractions with the observer (observation), are necessarily structural interactions in the space of the components. Therefore, when an observer refers to the organization of a composite unity, he refers to the rela­tions which realize the concept that defines the class of unities to which the observed composite unity belongs.

State-determined system. A state-determined system whose changes of state, defined as structural changes without loss of identity (defining organization), are determined by the structure of the system and not by an independent perturbing agent. This is a universal con­stitutive feature of dynamic systems.

Consenual domain. A consensual domain is a domain of interlocked (intercalated and mutually triggering) se­quences of states, established and determined through ontogenic interactions between structurally plastic state-determined systems. A consensual domain can become established only when the plastic interacting systems are homeostatic systems that maintain con­stant their essential variables through their mutual in­teractions. Living systems do establish consensual do­mains through the maintenance of their living organization.

Phenomenlogical domain. Domain of interactions specified by the properties of the interacting unities, regardless of whether these unities are simple or com­posite. Therefore, when a unity is defined, through the specification of its organization or by pointing to its pro­perties, a phenomenological domain is defined.

Purpose

After these preliminary considerations, and given that living systems exist and that some of them have a ner­vous system, the two aims of this article can now be precisely stated as follows.

(a) To explain the organization of living systems by describing the organization that constitutes a system as an autonomous unity that can, in principle, generate all the phenomenology proper to living systems if the adequate historical contingencies are given.

(b) To explain the organization of the nervous system by describing the organization that makes a neuronal network, integrated as a component subsystem in an organism, a system that can generate all the phenomenology proper to a nervous system.

Theory

AUTOPOIESIS latin

Living systems are given and they generate a specific phenomenology, the phenomenology of living systems. Therefore, in order to explain living systems it is necessary and sufficient to point to the organization that defines a class of unities that generates a phenomenology indistinguishable from the phenomenology proper to living systems. Such an organization can be described as follows.

There is a class of mechanistic systems in which each member of the class is a dynamic system defined as a unity by relations that constitute it as a network of processes of production of components which: (a) recur­sively participate through their interactions in the generation and realization of the network of processes of production of components which produced them; and (b) constitute this network of processes of production of components as a unity in the space in which they (the components) exist by realizing its boundaries.

Such systems I call autopoietic systems: the organization of an autopoietic system is the autopoietic organization. An autopoietic system that exists in the physical space is a living system (Maturana & Varela, 1973; Varela, Maturana & Uribe, 1974).

As a result of their organization, autopoietic systems operate as homeostatic systems that have their own organization as the critical fundamental variable that they actively maintain constant. In an autopoietic system all its (dynamic) states are states in autopoiesis and lead to autopoiesis. In this sense, autopoietic systems are closed systems, and, as a result of this, all the phenomenology of autopoietic systems is necessarily subservient to their autopoiesis, and a given phenomenon is a biological phenomenon only to the ex­tent to which it involves the autopoiesis of at least one living system.

NERVOUS SYSTEM

The nervous system is given as a network of interact­ing neurons that generates a phenomenology subser­vient to the autopoiesis of the organism in which it is embedded. Therefore, in order to explain the nervous system as a system, it is necessary and sufficient  to point to the organization that defines a neuronal  net­work that generates a phenomenology indistinguish­able from the phenomenology proper to the nervous system as it exists as a constitutive component of an autopoietic system. Such organization can be described as follows.

The nervous system is defined as a unity (that is, as a system) by relations that constitute it as a closed net­work of interacting neurons such that any change in the state of relative activity of collection of neurons leads to a change in the state of relative activity of other or the same collection of neurons: all states of neuronal activi­ty in the nervous system always lead to other states of activity in the nervous system.

A closed neuronal network does not have input or out­put surfaces as features of its organization, and although it can be perturbed through the interactions of its components, for it, in its operation as a system, there are only its own states of relative neuronal activity, regardless of what the observer may say about their origin. Given a closed system, inside and outside exist only for the observer who beholds it, not for the system. The sensory and the effector surfaces that an observer can describe in an actual organism, do not make the ner­vous system an open neuronal network because the en­vironment (where the observer stands) acts only as an intervening element through which the effector and sen­sory neurons interact completing the closure of the system.

If the observer, either experimentally or conceptually, were to open the nervous system at some synaptic sur­face, and describe the transfer properties of the system thus obtained in terms of  input  and output  relations, he would have an open network, but not a nervous system. This is what in fact happens when the observer describes the organism as a system which has indepen­dent sensory and effector surfaces for its interactions with the environment: he opens the nervous system and destroys its organization, leaving only an open neuronal network that can be described in terms of hierarchical transfer functions which are relevant only for the descriptive system of references introduced by the observer, who describes the changes of state of the ner­vous system by mapping them upon the changes of state of the environment (observable medium). As a closed neuronal network, however, the state-determined system that the nervous system is operated by generating relations of neuronal activity determined by its structure, regardless of environmental cir­cumstances. The observable effectiveness that the rela­tions of neuronal activity generated by the nervous system have for the realization of the autopoiesis of the organism under environmental perturbations results from the structural correspondence that actually exists between nervous system and organism, and between these and the medium in which the autopoiesis of the organism is realized.

IMPLICIT REQUIREMENTS

An autopoietic system is a state-determined com­posite dynamic unity. Therefore, although the characterization of an autopoietic system does not re­quire any statement about the characteristics of the medium in which the autopoiesis is realized, the actual realization of an autopoietic system in the physical space requires of a medium that provides the physical elements that permit the processes of production of components to take place. This medium includes all that is operationally different from the autopoietic unity, that is, all that at some instances may constitute a perturbation, even components of the system itself. It is, then, an implicit constitutive condition for autopoiesis that the autopoietic unity exists in a medium within which it interacts, and within which an observer can see it interchange elements with an environment.

PLASTICITY AND STRUCTURAL COUPLING

The interactions of a composite unity in the space of its components are interactions through its com­ponents, that is, are structural interactions. If as a result of a structural interaction the components of a unity, or their relations, change, the structure of the unity changes, and, if these structural changes occur without a change in the organization of the unity, the identity of the unity remains invariant. A unity whose structure can change while its organization remains invariant is a plastic unity, and the structural interactions under which this invariance can be sustained are perturba­tions. Since the changes of state of an autopoietic system are determined by its structure, the  perturba­tions under which the autopoietic unity undergoes its changes of state (changes of structure without loss of identity) constitutes only triggering events that couple the sequence of the changes of state of the autopoietic unity to the sequence of the changes of state of the medium that constitute the perturbations. Given that it is a constitutive feature of an autopoletlc unity to homeostatically maintain  invariant  its  organization under conditions of structural change, the realization of the autopoiesis of a plastic autopoietic unity under con­ditions of perturbations generated by a changing medium, necessarily results either  in the establishment in the autopoietic unity of a structure that can generate specific changes of state that can be triggered  by specific perturbing changes  of  state of  the medium, or in its disintegration. The result of the establishment of  this dynamic structural correspondance, or structural coupling, is the effective spatio-temporal correspon­dance of changes of state of the organism with the recurrent changes of state of the medium while the organism remains autopoietic.

The same arguments can be applied to the nervous system whose organization must be invariant, but whose structures needs not be so and may be plastic, with a dynamic of structural change coupled to the dynamic of structural change of other systems such as the organism which it integrates, and through this, to the medium in which this exists. In fact, if the structure of the nervous system changes, the domain of the possi­ble states of neuronal activity of the nervous system, and, hence, the domain of the possible behavioural states of the organism itself, change too. Therefore, if as a result of the structural changes of the nervous system the organism can go on in autopoiesis, the new nervous system’s structure obtained may constitute the basis for a new structural change which may also permit the organism to go on in autopoiesis. In principle, this process can be recursively repeated endlessly along the life of an organism, and generate a process of con­tinuous structural transformation that specifies the relations of neuronal activity that the nervous system generates in its participation in the autopoiesis. The consequences of this structural coupling are threefold:

(a) while the autopoiesis lasts, the changing struc­ture of the nervous system is necessarily that which generates the state of relative neuronal activity that par­ticipate in the continued autopoiesis of the organism in the medium in which it exists;

(b) while the autopoiesis lasts, the nervous system operates as an homeostatic system that generates rela­tions of neuronal activity that are subordinated to and determined by the actual realization of the autopoiesis of the organism which it integrates;

(c) while the autopoiesis lasts, the structural coupl­ing of the nervous system to the organism and medium, revealed as a spatio-temporal correspondance between the changes of state of the organism and the changes of state of the medium (recursively including the organism and the nervous system itself), appear to an observer as a semantic coupling.

In general, then, the reciprocal structural coupling of the organism and nervous system, and their simul­taneous structural coupling to the medium in which the autopoiesis is realized, are necessary consequences of the continued autopoiesis of the organism when these systems have plastic structures.

ONTOGENY  AND EVOLUTION

The history of structural changes without loss of identity in an autopoietic unity is its ontogeny. The coupling of the changing structure of an autopoietic uni­ty to the changing structure of the medium in which it exists, is ontogenic adaptation. The ontogenic adapta­tion of the nervous system is learning; or, in other words, given that the structure of the nervous system is plastic and that the nervous system is subservient to the autopoiesis of the organism which it integrates, the determination through structural coupling along the on­togeny of the organism of the relations of neuronal ac­tivity that the nervous system generates or maintains invariant, is the phenomenon of learning. In general, then, due to the homeostatic nature of the autopoietic organization that ensures that this organization is actively maintained constant, while the structure of the organism changes, ontogenic adaptation, and learning if there is nervous system, are necessary conse­quences of ontogeny: if ontogenic structural coupling of organism, nervous system and medium do not take place, the autopoietic system disintegrates. The same argument applies to the history of structural change of reproductively generated autopoietic activities. Such a history is organic evolution.

DESCRIPTIVE FALLACY

The process of structural coupling between two or more state-determined systems, one of which, at least, is autopoietic, as a historical process leading to the spatio-temporal coincidence between the changes of state of the coupled systems, arises as a necessary spontaneous consequence of the mutual operative restrictions to which the state-determined systems sub­mit to each other during their interactions without loss of identity. This spatio-temporal coincidence in the changes of state of the coupled systems, however, is usually described by the observers as a semantic coupl­ing, that is, as if it were the result of the computation by the autopoietic system (the organism) of its own ade­quate changes of state after gathering the proper infor­mation from the environment; in other words, as if the changes of state of the autopoietic system were deter­mined by the environment. Such a description, though, does not reflect any phenomenon actually taking place among state determined systems: (a) because the notion of information is valid only in the descriptive do­main as an expression of the cognitive uncertainty  of the observer, and does not represent any component ac­tually operant in any mechanistic phenomenon in the physical space; and (b), because the changes of state of a state determined system, be it autopoietic or not, are determined by its structure, regardless of whether these changes of state are adequate or not for some purpose that the observer may consider applicable. Therefore, any description which implies a semantic coupling be­tween structurally coupled state-determined systems, and which is not intended as a mere metaphor, is intrin­sically inadequate and fallacious.

Implications

The fact that, as the previous characterizations show, an autopoietic system in the physical space, and the nervous system that may be one of its component sub­systems, are closed systems, determines the occurence of three distinct phenomenological domains that can be described as follows:

(a) the domain of the internal changes of state of a system in which all state transitions occur without the system losing its identity;

(b) the domain of perturbations of a system in which the system can interact through its components in the space in which it exists as a unity and, as a result, undergoes changes of structure without loss of identity; and,

(c) the domain of interactions of a system as a (non­ composite) unity in the space which its properties as a unity define, regardless of how these properties arise.

The first phenomenological domain is the domain of realization of a system as a system; in the case of an autopoietic system this domain is the domain of its autopoiesis to which everything in it is subordinated as a necessary condition for its existence; in the case of the nervous system this domain is the domain of its operation as a closed neuronal network. The second phenomenological domain is the domain of structural coupling of the organism and the nervous system to each other and to the medium in which the autopoiesis of the organism is realized, and, therefore, the domain in which the structural phenomena that we describe as adaptation and learning occur. The third phenomeno­logical domain is the domain where cognition takes place as a phenomenon of observable manipulations of an environment, and where the observer arises as a system that can make descriptions, and always remain external to its circumstances by treating descriptions as objects of further descriptions.

The following are some general implications of this.

(a) If the autopoiesis of an autopoietic unity is real­ized through a distributed structure that ensures a distributed autopoiesis, a simple mechanical fragmen­tation of the autopoietic unity (self-division or reproduction) produces at least two new autopoietic unities that may have identical or different structures according to how uniform was the component’s distribution in the original unity. Heredity of  organization and structure with the possibility of hereditary structural change is, therefore, a necessary conse­quence of distributed autopoiesis. If there is differential realization of autopoiesis among structurally different autopoietic unities due to disuniformities in the medium in which they exist, evolution is a necessary conse­quence if the autopoietic unities are generated through self-division.

(b) All the states that an autopoietic system can adopt are states in autopoiesis, and are necessarily determined by its organization and structure, not by the perturbations arising in the medium in which it exists. Cognition, at whatever level of concreteness or abstrac­tion, as a phenomenon of operation of the organism (as a unity) in its medium, also necessarily consists at the level of the internal dynamics of the unity in the actual realization of its autopoiesis. Therefore, in a strict sense, for any organism its cognitive domain is its ac­tual domain of autopoiesis.

(c) If two plastic autopoietic systems interact, and their structures become ontogenetically coupled as a result of these interactions, a consensual domain of conduct is developed between the two organisms as a domain of conduct in which the participation that the conduct of one organism has for the realization of the autopoiesis of the other organism becomes determined during the interactions through their structural coupl­ing. Such a consensual domain of conduct is a linguistic domain, and as such it is a domain of descriptions in which the conduct of one organism can be taken by an observer as a description of the consensual conduct which it elicits in the other organism.

(d) If an organism is capable of consensual conduct and of recursively interacting with its own states (through internal interactions of its closed nervous system), and applies the descriptive operation to itself by developing a consensual domain with itself through interactions with its own consensual states, a new phenomenological domain is generated that is in­distinguishable from that which we call our domain of self-consciousness.

Comments

THE OBSERVER

Everything said is said by an observer to another observer; furthermore, the observer can always recur­sively be an observer of his observation and stay exter­nal to the description of his circumstances. This he can do because everything he does is mapped in the same domain: the domain of relative neuronal activity in his closed nervous system. Interactions of the nervous system with its own states of neuronal activity allow, in principle, for infinite recursion with continuous behavioural change. The domain of descriptions in which the observer arises when in the course of evolu­tion the nervous system becomes able to recursively in­teract with its own states, is also a closed domain.

THE THEORY

The purpose of this theory is to give the fundamental set of necessary and sufficient notions capable of ex­plaining all the phenomenology of living systems. Therefore, no attempt has been made to explain any par­ticuIar biological phenomenon; all particular phenomena should be explainable by the theory if the proper contingent circumstances of their realization are taken into consideration.  Also, I have made no attempt to give this theory a mathematical formalism, first, because I am incompetent to do it, and second, because I consider that such formalism is necessarily secondary to the complete conceptual statement of the theory which I have here presented.

Basic requirements that the theory satisfies are as follows.

(a) To use only simple operative concepts of im­mediate validity to any observer as a natural and as a scientific person.

(b) To state only necessary conditions that cannot be taken for granted. Thus, when talking of processes of production of components (such as molecules, polymers, etc.) no statement is made about their physical or chemical legality, obviously because in nature there only occur those chemical reactions or physical processes that can occur. Therefore, if a given set of components cannot generate the processes that constitute an autopoietic system, they do not constitute an autopoietic system, without this invalidating the no­tion of autopoiesis. A truism is implicit: autopoiesis takes place whenever it can take place.

(c) To specify only the conditions which generate phenomena that are isomorphic with the phenomena to be explained, and not with the description of the phenomena as they appear to the observer.

(d) To provide a mechanistic explanation for all biological phenomena, that is, to show that all biological phenomena arise from the interactions of the proper components, and not as an expression of the properties of some components.

(e) To point to conditions that can be realized through neighborhood relations without invoking organizing principles of any kind which pretend to subordinate the components to the whole. The unity, the whole, is the result of the interactions of the components through the realization of the organization that defines it, and not an operant factor in the interaction of the components that generate it. For the purpose of communication, an observer that beholds simultaneously the unity and its components may describe the latter with reference to the former, but this Is merely a descriptive metaphor and not a reflection of the constitution of the unity. A unity if composite, is fully specified by specifying its organization.

To the extent that these basic requirements have  been fulfilled, the theory reveals living systems as hav­ing a fundamentally simple organization which can arise spontaneously, and inevitably, in any part of the universe when  certain conditions are given. All the structural complexity of present-day living  systems is the result of their evolutionary and ontogenic histories, and, therefore, irrelevant to the description of their organization.

POINTING TO A UNITY

The basic operation that an observer performs (although this operation is not exclusive to observers) is the operation of distinction; that is, the pointing to a uni­ty by performing an operation which defines its boun­daries and separates it from a background. The  observer, then, always specifies the unity that he observes through some explicit or implicit operation of distinction, and always implies by his observation an organization in it that is compatible with its implied or specified boundaries if it is a composite unity. This is a fundamental point for three reasons.

(a) Given an operation of distinction that separates a unity by specifying its boundaries, usually there are many organizations that could define a unity with such boundaries as partial boundaries, but which would strictly specify different unities. There is, therefore, a communicative ambiguity in pointing to a unity if no ex­plicit reference is made to its organization or to its be­ing indicated through a total distinction, and two observers may disagree because through unspecified boundaries they may imply different unities, even though they may perform identical overt operations of partial distinction under the belief that they refer to the same unity.

(b) Different operations of total distinction separate different kinds of unities because they define different kinds of boundaries and, therefore, imply different organizations.

(c) The organization and structure of a unity specify all the operations of distinction through which it can be separated from the background.

It follows that it is always the task of the observer to specify the organization of the unity that he observes, or to imply it unambiguously through a complete operation of distinction.

THE PHYSICAL SPACE

I have said that living systems are autopoietic systems that exist in the physical space. Strictly, however, I should say that the physical space is the space in which living systems exist, and that this deter­mines its singularity. In fact, since autopoietic systems are closed homeostatic systems that maintain constant their organization, all their changes of state are changes of state in autopoiesis and they can only be perturbed through the interactions of their components. Therefore the domain of perturbations of an autopoietic system is defined by the domain of interactions of its com­ponents, and exists as a domain of perturbations only in the domain in which these   components exist. This necessarily applies to us too, and, unless we explicitly suppose something different, this also applies to our cognitive processes. It follows that if cognitive pro­cesses are operations in autopoiesis, the space of our components is a limiting space outside of which we cannot step through cognition.

The physical space defined as the space in which liv­ing systems exist, then, is both ontologically and epistemologically singular; it is ontologically singular because it is constitutive to the phenomenology of liv­ing systems, and it is epistemologically singular because it defines the operational boundaries of our cognitive domain.

STRUCTURAL COUPLING

Two plastic systems become structurally coupled as a result of their sequential interactions when their respective structures undergo sequential changes without loss of identity. Therefore, the structural coupl­ing of two independent structurally plastic unities is a necessary consequence of their interactions, and is greater the more interactions take place. If one of the plastic systems is an organism and the other its medium, the result is ontogenic adaptation of the organism to its medium. If the two plastic systems are organisms, the result of the ontogenic structural coupl­ing is a consensual domain, that is, a domain of behaviour in which the structurally determined changes of state of the coupled organisms correspond to each other in interlocked sequences.

To an observer, the states of adaptation between organisms and environment, or between organisms in a consensual domain, appear as states of correspon­dance between plastic systems that can be described in terms of functional relations, that is as semantic coupl­ings. The statements go like this: the function of such and such a structure in the organism is to cause such and such a change in the environment; or the meaning of the state of system A for system B is what deter­mines the state to which system B passes as a result of the interaction of the two systems. Such a description in terms of functional relations is a description in terms of a semantic coupling because the structural cor­respondance between the interacting systems is con­sidered without reference to its origin, and the changes of state of the coupled systems are treated as if they were determined externally by the  perturbations, and not internally by the respective present structures of the interacting systems. If the fact that the mutual perturba­tions constitute only the historical instances under which the structurally coupled system undergo internal­ly determined changes of state is neglected, four fun­damental phenomena are ignored.

(a) That the result of the structural coupling of two or more systems is the structural determination of an in­terlocked order in the respective changes of state of the systems that is realized in the form of ordered se­quences of mutually triggering perturbations.

(b) That if it were not the case that perturbations only constitute triggering circumstances for internally deter­mined changes of state, inadequate behaviour, that is behaviour that for an observer appears out of context, would never take place.

(c) That semantic interactions, that is, interactions in which the perturbing agent determines the new state at­tained by the perturbed system, so not take place in the phenomenological domains of state determined systems, but only  occur in the domain of description.

(d) That the domain of descriptions arises as a metadomain from the establishment of consensual do­mains by structurally coupled plastic systems (Maturana, 1970). Although the structural coupling is a historical process, that is, each structural innovation arises as a modification of a pre-existing structure and constitutes the basis for the next one, the structurally coupled unities always correspond to each other in the present. The history of a system may reveal how its structure arose, but it does not reveal how it operates in the present: the operation of a system is always the result of its present structure, not of its history, however, significant or complex this operation may seem in a historical perspective.

The nervous system operates in the present as a closed neuronal network that maintains constant, under continuous external (changes in the medium) and inter­nal (its own states of neuronal activity) perturbations, certain relations of neuronal activity (describable either as internal neuronal correlations or as sensory-effector correlations) that have been specified or become specified through its structural coupling with the organism. If one considers the complexity of the things that people are able to do, such as talking, abstract thinking or ethical or political decisions, such a descrip­tion of the nervous system seems insufficient. This in­sufficiency, however, is only apparent because the ethical, sociological or philosophical complexity of these human operations lies in their historical significance, not in the nature of the operations themselves.

The historical significance and, hence, the contextual complexity of any behaviour, is put in the descriptions by the observer who defines the domain of relevance of the observed behaviour in his domain of description. Relevance, meaning, function, significance, then, are terms which refer to the observable domain of interac­tions of the autopoietic unity as a unity, and not to its in­ternal autopoietic changes of state. Therefore, the ac­tual complexity of the operation of the nervous system is, exclusively, the complexity of an homeostatic closed neuronal activity that may be continuously changing through the structural coupling of the system to the medium (which may recursively include the nervous system itself) in which it exists.

SELF-REPRODUCTION

If the organization of an autopoietic unity and the structure which realizes it are uniformly distributed across the expanse of the unity through a uniform distribution of components, self-reproduction is a trivial consequence of a simple mechanical fragmentation of the autopoietic unity, and heredity a necessary conse­quences of the uniform distribution of the components. In modern cells there are molecular components that are usually not uniformly distributed across the cell due to its internal compartmentalization, and must become uniformly distributed (through the dynamics of mitosis) before cellular fragmentation takes place. However, once the uniform distribution of components is ob­tained, everything occurs as stated above. No copying takes place, and no notion of program, of coding or transmission of information is necessary in order to ac­ count for the phenomena of self-reproduction and heredity.

Since it is the autopoietic organization that deter­mines the unity of a living system, and since it is its structure that determines its mode of realization, it is in­trisically inadequate to consider any particular compo­nent as responsible of the properties of the system, and, least of all, of its hereditary characteristics. Notions such as program,coding or transmission of information do not apply to the operation of state-determined systems. These notions are useful, though conceptually misleading, as metaphors in the domain of description in which a mapping is made of the observed phenomenon upon the domain of purposeful design of the observer. An autopoietic unity, as is universally the case with every state-determined system, undergoes on­ly the changes of state determined by its structure. The viral DNA that is sometimes referred to as a genetic message, does not specify what the host cell will do; the changes of state that the cell underdoes are determined by the structure of the cell under viral perturbation, but not by the viral DNA.

DESCRIPTIONS

A consensual domain ontogenically established through the structural coupling between two or more organisms appears to an observer as an interlocked do­main of distinctions, indications or descriptions, according to how he considers the behaviour of, the observed organisms. If the observer considers every distinguishable behaviour as a representation of the en­vironmental circumstances which trigger it, he con­siders the behaviour as a description, and the consen­sual domain in which this behaviour takes place as a do­main of interlocked descriptions of actual environmen­tal states. What we do as observers when we make a description is exactly that, we behave in an interlocked manner with other observers in a consensual domain ontogenically generated through our direct (mother­ child relation) or indirect (membership in the same society) structural coupling. Yet, if the observer forgets that the interlocked adequacy of the mutually triggering changes of state of the mutually perturbing systems in the consensual domain is the result of their ontogenic structural coupling, he may describe the consensual do­main as if it constituted an intrinsic descriptive system in which the descriptive interactions gave information to the organisms to compute the ad hoc states needed to handle the described environment.

The establishment of a domain of descriptions is not exclusive of autopoietic i;iystems. Any collection of systems that can undergo ontogenic structural coupling can establish a consensual domain as a closed domain of interlocked interactions and, therefore, can par­ticipate in a domain of descriptions in which every description is a description only within the consensual domain. Furthermore, if a system that can make descriptions can be perturbed by its own states within the do­main of descriptions, and thus generate descriptions of a medium that includes its descriptions, a second-order consensual domain is produced through the recursive application of descriptions on descriptions, and an observer is operationally generated. For this to take place, however, it is necessary that all perturbing agents, including the descriptions, should belong to the same class, so that the operation of description could be recursively applied to the product of its application. This is possible in organisms with a nervous system because the nervous system is a close neuronal net­ work in which all states of activity are states of relative neuronal activity that only lead to other states of relative neuronal activity, independently of the circumstances of interactions of the organism in which these states of activity arise, a condition which necessarily results in the nervous system becoming recursively structurally coupled to its own structural changes. Since internally and externally generated states of relative neuronal ac­tivity in the nervous system are indistinguishable for the dynamics of states of the nervous system, the interac­tions of the nervous system with its own states that its closed organization implies, become, in the domain of interactions of the organism, descriptions of descrip­tions.

LINGUISTIC DOMAIN

A linguistic domain is a domain of consensual behaviour, ontogenically established between at least two structurally plastic organisms, that is usually described as a domain of semantic interactions. Yet, the semantic value of an interaction, in whatever domain, is not a property of the interaction, but a feature of the description that the observer makes by referring to it as if the changes of state of the interacting systems were determined by their mutual perturbations, and not by their respective individual structures. Therefore, the problem of establishing a linguistic domain is not the problem of establishing an operational semantic coupl­ing, but the problem of establishing an ontogenic structural coupling that generates a consen­sual domain in which the coupled plastic systems can undergo an unending series of interlocked alternating changes of state. In other words, linguistic behaviour is structurally determined behaviour in ontogenically structurally coupled organisms, in which the structural coupling determines the sequential order of the mutual­ly triggering alternating changes of state. Semantics ex­ists only in a metadomain of descriptions as a property projected upon the interacting systems by the observer, and valid only for him.

Descriptions as linguistic behaviour are no exception to this. The semantic value of a description exists only in a recursively-generated metadomain of descriptions of descriptions, not in the domain of operation in which a description is realized as an actual behaviour. The same happens with self-consciousness as a subdomain of self-descriptions in a domain of descriptions of descriptions (Maturana, 1970). In these  circumstances, the changes of state of the nervous system that lead to self-description would not be different from other changes of state that lead to other descriptions, but would differ only in the consensual domain in which the descriptions arose and are applied.

It is the recursive application of descriptions in a do­main of self-descriptions as the expression of a recur­sive structural coupling of the nervous system with its own structure in the sequential changes of state of a single system, that gives to self-consciousness its un­canny quality of a process which transforms a single system into two: the changes of state of a single system appear to an observer as if they were taking place through interactions with another. Otherwise, as occurs with any other behaviour, the determination of self-consciousness is structural and not semantic.

Conclusions

Although the fundamental conclusions are already contained in the previous sections, it may be worthwhile to summarize them in the following form.

(a)  The constitutive feature of a living system is autopoiesis in the physical space; the constitutive feature of the nervous system is its condition of being a closed neuronal network.

(b) All changes of state in the living system and in its nervous system are subordinated to the realization of the autopoiesis of the living system, if this does not oc­cur the autopoiesis stops and the living system disintegrates.

(c) If the organism and its nervous system are struc­turally plastic, the continuous realization of the autopoiesis of the organism necessarily results in a structural coupling of the organism and nervous system to each other, and to the medium in which the autopoiesis is realized.

(d) The result of this structural coupling is that although the organism operates only in autopoiesis, and the nervous system operates only in generating internal relations of neuronal activity, each determined by its own structure, the changes of state of the organism and the nervous system, and the changes of state of the medium, mutually trigger each other in a manner that leads to continued autopoiesis. As a result, if an organism were to be taken out of the medium to which it is structurally coupled, it would go on in its structurally determined changes of state regardless of their inade­quacy to the changes of state of the new medium, and, eventually, disintegrate.

(e) Descriptions in terms of information transfer, coding and computations of adequate states, are fallacious because they only reflect the observer’s do­main of purposeful design and not the dynamics of the system as a state-determined system.

(f) The observable complexities of the domain of in­teractions of an autopoietic unity as a unity, are com­plexities proper to the historical circumstances in which the changes of state of the unity take place, not to the processes that constitute the internal changes of state of the unity itself, the nervous system included. The organization and structure of an autopoietic unity do not include operational elements proper to the do­main in which it interacts as a unity.

(g) Any recursive operation in an organism, or in its nervous system, is the application of the same operation on different states of a structurally changing system with invariant organization, that can take place only because the results of the application of the repeated operation is applied. This is what obviously takes place in the nervous system which, as a closed neuronal network, only adopts states of relative neuronal activity that lead to new states of relative neuronal activity. Such a recursion in the descriptive do­main is necessary to generate self-consciousness as a new phenomenological domain.

References

Maturana, H. R. (1970). Neurophysiology of cognition. In Cognition a Multiple View, Paul Garvin  (Ed.) Pp. 3-23. New York: Spartan Books.

Maturana, H. R. & Varela, F. G. (1973). De maquinas y seres vivos. Editorial Universitaria, Santiago, Chile.

Varela, F. G. & Maturana, H. R. & Uribe, R. B. (1974). Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems; its characterization and a model. Biosystems, 5, 185.


Self-Organization of Living Systems:

A Formal Model of Autopoiesis

Milan Zeleny

The Joseph A. Martino Graduate School of Business Administration
Fordham University at Lincoln Center
New  York, NY 10023

(Received August 9, 1976; In final form November  15,  1976)

[The article first appeared in International Journal of General Systems, Vol. 4, No. 1, 1977 published by Gor­don and Breach Science Publishers, Ltd. We appreciate the permission of the publisher to re-typeset the article.]

A formalization, computerization and extension of the original Varela-Maturana-Uribe model of autopoiesls is presented.  Autopoietic systems are driven by sets of simple “rules” which guide the behavior of components in a given milieu. These rules are capable of pro­ducing systemic structures that are far more complex than we could ever achieve by a direct arrangement of  components, i.e., by a  method of systems analysis and design. The study of autopoietic systems indicates that the traditional emphasis on internal qualities of svstem’s components has been misplaced. It is the organization of components, rather than components themselves (or their structural manifestations), that provides the necessary and sufficient conditions of autopoiesis and thus of life itself. The dynamic autonomy of autopoietic systems contrasts significantly with the non-autonomous, allopoietic mechanistic systems.

INDEX TERMS Autopoiesis, allopoiesis, autogenesis, biological clock, social autopoiesis, human systems management, production, disintegration, bonding, catalytic neighborhood, APL-autopoiesis.

1 Introduction

In 1974 three Chilean scientists, F. G. Varela, H. R. Maturana and  R. B. Uribe, published a seminal article,1 entitled “Autopoiesis: The Organization of Living Systems, Its Characterization and A Model,” providing a new direction as well as a new hope in contemporary theory of living systems. Their work could represent the first significant advance toward the general theory of organizations since the advents of Trentowski’s Cybernetyka 2, Bogdanov’s Tectology,Leduc’s Syn­thetic Biology,4 Smuts’ Holism5 and von Hayek’s Spon­taneous Social Orders.6

In this article we deal with organic systems, i.e., both biological and social organizations displaying the fuzzi­ly defined quality called “life.” They are characterized by their self-renewal, self-maintenance and stability in a given environmental domain. The process of a con­tinuous self-renewal of a systemic whole is called autopoiesis, i.e., self-production.

Autopoietic organization is realized as an autonomous and self-maintaining unity through an in­dependent network of component-producing processes such that the components, through their interaction, generate recursively the same network of processes which produced them.

The product of an autopoietic organization is thus not different from the organization itself. A cell produces cell-forming molecules, an organism keeps renewing its defining organs, a social group “produces” group­ maintaining individuals, etc. Such autopoietic systems are organizationally closed and structurally state­ determined,7,8, with no apparent inputs and outputs.

In contrast, the product of an allopoietic organization is different from the organization itself, it does not pro­duce the components and processes which would realize it as a distinct unity. Thus, allopoietic systems are not perceived as “living” and are usually referred to as mechanistic or contrived systems. Their organization is open, i.e., with apparent inputs and outputs. For ex­ample, spatially determined structures, like crystals or macromolecular chains, machines, formal hierarchies, etc., are allopoietic.

It is important to distinguish between organization and structure of an organic system in this context. We shall paraphrase the original thoughts advanced by Maturana and Varela.9,10

A given system, observed as a distinct unity in its en­vironment domain, can be viewed as a whole of inter­related and further unspecified components.

A network of interactions between the components, renewing the system as a distinct unity, constitutes the organization of the system. The actual spatial arrange­ment of components and their relations, integrating the system temporarily in a given physical milieu, con­stitutes its structure.

The unity and holism of systemic organization and structure represents what is commonly referred to as a system.

Thus, two distinct systems may have the same organization but different structures. Structural changes do not reflect changes in the system as a unity as long as its organization remains invariant. A system and its organization cannot be explained by simply reproducing its structure. The structure of a system determines the way its components interact between themselves, with their environment and with the observer.

Organizationally closed systems are not structurally separated from their environment; they are interacting and coupled with it. Although they do not have inputs or outputs, they can be externally perturbed and undergo structural adaptations. Any autopoietic system can be perceived as being allopoietic by specifying its in­put/output surfaces, i.e., by disconnecting its organiza­tional closure, either experimentally or mentally.

Allopoietic systems are organizationally open, they produce something different than themselves. Their boundaries are observer-dependent, their input and out­ put surfaces connect them mechanically with their en­vironment. Their purpose, as an interpretation of their input/output relation, lies solely in the domain of the observer.

Further discussions along the above lines can be found in a variety of related works.11-14

2 Autopoietic Model Of A Cell

One of the simplest autopoietic systems exhibiting the minimum organization of components necessary for autopoiesis, is a model of a biological cell. There is a catalytic nucleus capable of interaction with the medium of substrate so that the membrane-forming components can be continually produced. The resulting structure displays a membraneous boundary that defines the system as a separate and autonomous unity in the space of its components.

In accordance with this basic organization of a cell, the simplest model of its autopoiesis must consist of a medium of substrate, a catalyst capable of producing more complex components-links, which are in turn capable of bonding, ultimately concatenating into a membrane surrounding the catalyst.

We shall designate the basic components of the model by the following symbols:

The original Varela-Maturana-Uribe model1 was based on the following organization of components:

2.1 Production

A catalyst and two units of substrate produce a free link and a hole, while the catalyst is assumed to be essentially unaffected by this operation. Pro­duction can take place when a pair of substrate is in the predetermined neighborhood of the catalyst.  Catalytic “reach” or the strength of  and its dynamics can be effectively simulated.

2.2 Disintegration

Any link, free or bonded, can disintegrate into two units of substrate. Additional unit of substrate will occupy an available hole which must be in the neighborhood of a disintegrating component.

2.3 Bonding 

A free link can bond with a chain of bonded links; two chains of bonded links can be bonded into one, or re-bonded after their connecting link has disintegrated; two free links can be bonded together to start a chain formation.

Observe that disintegration and bonding are opera­tions that do not require catalyst; they are “self-catalytic.” That does not mean that the catalyst has no influence over those operations. For example, bonding can take place only beyond a predetermined catalytic neighborhood while disintegration can appear anywhere in the space.

More detailed rules, guiding the movement of all com­ponents and specifying the necessary conditions for the three interactive rules above, are discussed in the next section. Spontaneous encounters, bonding and disintegration of components is partially guided by chance. We shall only briefly summarize some addi­tional properties.1,13,15,16

Each component (and its corresponding neighbor­ hood) is allowed to move over the space according to predetermined rules. A set of dominance relations must be established in order to prevent different components claiming the same space during the same unit time­ interval. Any component can claim a hole, a link can displace a substrate, and a catalyst can displace both substrates and links. Thus  (space) es­tablishes this partial dominance. We ao not allow any movement  of bonded links.

Each link can have at most two bonds: it can be either free, , single bonded, , or fully bonded,. Additional bonds,  , are of course possible, but they induce frequent branching of chains, creating thus catalyst-free enclosures. Multiple  bonds  are indispensable for modeling in a three dimensional space.

Unbranched chains of bonded links will ultimately form a membrane around the catalyst, creating the enclosure impenetrable for bothand . These two components are thus effectively “trapped” and forced to function for the benefit of the autopoietic unity. Substrate units,  , can pass freely through the mem­brane and thus keep the catalyst supplied for the production of additional . Any disintegrated links, caus­ing ruptures in the membrane, and thus be readily and effectively repaired by the ongoing production. The uni­ty of the system is recursively maintained through a series of minor structural adaptations.

In Figure 1, we present a sample of APL printouts pro­viding typical “snapshots” from the “history” of an autopoietic unity.

3  A Formal Model of Autopoiesis

4  Experiments  in Self-Organization

Our formalization of a parallel process is very flexible. Catalytic neighborhoods can change their sizes and shapes, as well as the neighborhoods of other com­ ponents. The rates of production and disintegration can vary over time or in dependency on their previous values. Multiple catalysts can be introduced, stationary or In flux with respect to each other. The influence of chance can be further amplified or totally removed (by extending the set of movement rules). The amount of matter in the system can be kept either constant or ex­ ternal inflows and outflows of substrate introduced. The system can be induced to disintegrate totally or to “freeze” into a  stable  allopoietic  structure. Systems with turbulent behavior or only partially delineated membranes can be observed as well as the systems whose membranes are ever-expanding. Systems with broad or narrow membranes, substrate-seeking “amoebas” floating through space, and hundreds of other varieties can be evolved by adjusting and har­ monizing a few parameters or rules.

We can even provide a connection between a par­ticular structural adaptation and the change in the organization itself. The interacting rules, which are otherwise invariant, can be thus allowed to change ac­cording to  appropriate meta-rules. Such self-affecting systems are then capable of self-reproduction and therefore evolution.

We shall introduce a few simple experiments per­ formed with the APL-AUTOPOIESIS model.13

4.1  Function and Form

We already discussed the distinction between systemic organization and structure. The same autopoietic organization is realizable through different structural forms although its basic unity of function and its identi­ty as a unique system stay unchanged. Structural adap­tations are triggered by specific perturbing changes in its environment. Maturana talks about  structural coupling,7 i.e.,”the effective spatio-temporal cor­respondence of changes of state of the organism with the recurrent changes of state of the medium while the organism remains autopoietic.” This structural rapport of the system and its environment allows us to simulate complex structural histories, in a controlled and predic­table way, without changing system’s organization.

For example, such structural variables as size and shape can be simply studied. Changes in the catalytic neighborhood could elicit a large variety of structural responses, see some typical “snapshot” printouts in Figure 4.

Autopoiesis of a cell can be affected by a particular structural adaptation, its functions of production, disintegration and bonding affected to their extremes. An allopoietlc structure, a crystal, might ultimately form. It can neither disintegrate nor expand or move. Either a weak catalytic reach or a high inflow of substrate could lead to such “allopoietlzation.” On the other hand, an increased outflow of available substrate, creating disproportionately many holes, would cause the catalyst to move rapidly over the space and the tur­ bulence of its neighborhood would prevent orderly bonding-no membrane may ever form.

One can simulate a growth in system’s size quite simply by establishing a state-dependent change regime in the size of the catalytic neighborhood. Also, very complex shapes and patterns can be simulated as arising from structural adaptations of the autopoietic system. In Figure 5 observe an example of an autopoietic cell acquiring the shape of a cross. Theoretically, any complex shape can be induced to emerge  through induced  structural adaptations.

4.2 Biological Clock

All living systems exhibit a variety of biorhythms and cyclical adaptations. The most prominent is the aging phenomenon, a clearly observable “life cycle” of growth, plateau and decline. Organizational stability and permanence of an autopoietic system is the perm­anence and stability of its structural history, not of its existence. All known  autopoietic organizations have “built-in death.” They either crystallize into allopoietic debris or disintegrate back into their components.

No autopoietic cell can escape death. Observe that it is unreasonable to assurne that the catalyst is unaf­fected by its participation in the production of links. Each single act of production diminishes its catalytic power. Initially, when there is a lot of free substrate, the number of produced links is naturally very high. At the same time, the number of holes necessary for disin­tegration is still very low. As a result there is a large in­ itial build-up in the amount of organized matter (links, free or bonded). As the amount of free substrate decreases and the number of holes increases, the two rates, production and disintegration, achieve a balance which is characteristical for a relatively stable period of self-repairing membraneous enclosure. But the produc­tion must go on, although at much slower rate, and the more productions are performed the weaker the catalyst becomes. Thus, we experience the fastest “aging” of the catalyst in the initial stages of the most vigorous production activity. Although this “aging rate” becomes progressively slower, the production rate is ultimately exceeded by the disintegration rate and the total amount of organized matter starts to decline. Because the holes become fewer again and there is more substrate available, the aging and loss of catalytic power speeds up at this later stage in a burst of activity before total catalytic exhaustion. The disintegration rate is already low before the death itself becomes only a slow decay afterwards.13

There is a large variety of other emergent rhythms that can be identified in the behavior of this autopoietic cell. For example, there is a natural cycle observed in the ratio of holes to substrate even when the rates of production and disintegration are kept stable. More substrate leads to more links and higher incidence of bonding. Consequently, the actual amount of substrate is less while the number of holes is up. That allows more links to disintegrate, creating more substrate and fewer holes again.

It would be a gross fallacy to interpret such structural rapport between the system and it s environment as being due to some kind of a feedback mechanism. There is none. No information is transferred, none is coded. It only appears as such to an observer.

4.3  Multiple Catalysts

Obviously there can be any number of catalysts functioning in a given space. When they are distant enough they can enclose themselves quite independently and function without mutual interference. A group of autopoietic cells can be observed, each and all in a dynamic equilibrium with their environment.

The most interesting case arises if we assume that at a certain stage the catalyst is allowed to divide itself in­ to two identical replicas. For example, the first total closure of a membrane provides the trigger which causes such catalytic replication. The new catalyst then occupies any immediately adjacent hole. Their respec­tive neighborhoods overlap to a large extent. Note that a large portion of the original membrane will disintegrate because no re-bonding is possible in the area of the overlap. Because a catalyst cannot pass through bond­ed segments, it will ultimately float out of this new opening. The two catalysts of equal power will  float apart and gradually enclose themselves by two separate membranes. The larger is the overlap of their respective neighborhoods, the stronger is this initial “pulling apart.” Gradually they disconnect themselves, almost gently.13 See Figure 6.

Apparently a self-reproduction has occurred. There are two identical and independent autopoietic cells as a result of a simple mechanical division of a cell. A fairly close replica of the initial cell is obtained without the benefit of any copying, coding or information process­ing artifacts.

4.4 Autogenesis of Life: A Simple Scenario

We shall consider a uniformly distributed environment of basic particles of matter,•, devoid of any information and structure. Such universe is initially in a ther­modynamic equilibrium. Let us assume that there is a separate locality where the local values of the mean density and temperature can differ from the equilibrium conditions. Only the particles • can penetrate the boundaries of such locality, both ways. All other struc­turally higher combinations of the basic particles are trapped inside the boundaries.

The following set of rules (one of many possible) would induce a self-organization of an autopoietic unity (like a living cell) independently of particular chemical and structural properties of the basic components:

Observe that ultimately the density of substrate par­ticles  increases as it might be necessary for a cell to emerge. At the same time both the stable, and the unstable, compounds are being effectively trapped within the locality of disequilibrium. The chance of  is being steadily increased. When emerges, one or more, the cell can be produced accord­ ing to the rules we already studied. We can imagine that there are dormant and active layers of rules that are be­ing brought to their action by the emergence of the necessary particles, molecules or compounds. Finally, the last three rules allow for “self-regeneration” of the catalyst and its replication. That triggers the autopoietic division of the cell and induces self-reproduction.

Note that our fundamental particles, •, define space through their relationship and interaction. Thus space is only derived and an observer-dependent concept. It con­sists of a finite number of points in any of its neighborhoods and thus it is finite and discrete. Dirac suggested that space is filled with a sea of electrons oc­cupying ail energy levels up to the “Fermi level.” The electrons which we observe have risen above the Fermi level, leaving behind a “hole,” which is observed as a positively charged twin of the electron. The elementary particles of contemporary physics are continually emerging from and being reabsorbed into the “vacuum” of the Fermi sea. They are products of the underlying autopoiesis in the domain of fundamental substrate­ particles.

5   Social Autopoiesis

The range of applications of autopoiesis Is extending from atoms and molecules, organisms and nervous systems, language and communication, to social behavior, human societies, planning and management. At the same time the implications of autopoiesis are profound and often upsetting. The literature dealing with or related to autopoiesis is growing rapidly. We list some of the more important works in the References.1-8,35

We conclude with some thoughts on social autopoiesis. Human societies, and any other societies of autopoietic components, can maintain their cohesiveness and unity through the “rules of conduct” that are spontaneously generated by the autopoiesis of the components. F. A. Hayek21 emphasized  that  the order of social events, though it is the result of human action, has not been entirely created by men deliberate­ly arranging the elements in a preconceived pattern. If the forces or rules that bring about such spontaneous orders are understood, then such knowledge could be used to produce orders that are far more complex than those attempted by deliberately arranging all the ac­tivities of a complex society. This is not an argument against planning but rather against the simplistic tinker­ing and interfering with orders that are much too com­plex to be viewed as mechanical contrivances. S. Beer29 also reiterates the fact that if a social institution is autopoietic then it is necessarily ” alive,” i.e., it main­tains its identity in a biological sense.

Human systems, since they are not simple machines, should not be designed or analyzed. They should be managed. Manager is a catalyst of spontaneous social forces. Crystals are not produced by directly arranging the individual molecules, but by creating the conditions under which they form themselves. Plants or animals are not put together by designers. They are managed by inducing the conditions favorable to their growth. The task of human management is to stimulate a growth of network of decision processes, systems, programs and rules, i.e., an organization, which would be effective in attaining  institutional  objectives. Such growth process of an autopoietic unity evolves its own rules of change. These rules, in turn, determine the kinds of structural adaptations which could emerge.

Humans live their lives through human systems, shape them through their individual aspirations, goals, norms and actions, which could be quite different and independent of the individual ones. Humans are in turn continuously being shaped by such self-organized en­tities, their spatial and temporal arrangement evolving through a succession of state determined structures. Human actions and interaction with their emerging organization is irreducible to behavior, as it is so forcefully stated by E.Jantsch.30

5.1  Human Systems Management

A new mode of inquiry into complex human systems is being evolved-Human Systems Management. It is based on the following set of observations:

  1. Human systems are to be managed rather than analyzed or designed. HSM is not systems analysis or design.
  2. Management of human systems is a process of catalytic reinforcement of dynamic organization and bonding of individuals. HSM does not design a hierarchy of control and command.
  3. The components of human systems are HSM is not general systems theory but a general theory of human organizations.
  4. The integral complexity of human systems can be lost through the process of mathematical simplifica­tion. They can be studied through a relatively simple set of semantic rules, governing the self-organization of their complexity. HSM is not operations research, econometrics or applied mathematics.
  5. The interactions between individuals are not those of electronic circuitry, communication channels, or feedback loop mechanisms. HSM is not cybernetics or information theory of communication.
  6. The order of human organizations is maintained through their structural adaptations under the condi­tions of environmental disequilibrium. HSM is not the theory of general equilibrium.
  7. The concepts of optimization and optimal control are not meaningful in a general theory of human systems. Human aspirations and goals are dynamic, multiple and in continuous conflict. Such conflict is the very source of their catalysis. HSM is not optimal con­trol theory or theory of conflict resolution.
  8. The inquiry into human systems is trans­disciplinary by definition. Human systems encompass the whole hierarchy of natural systems: physical, biological, social and spiritual. HSM is not inter­disciplinary or multidisciplinary, it does not attempt to unify scientific disciplines, it transcends them.

It is appropriate to conclude by quoting S. Beer:29

” … the way an autopoietic system will respond to a gross en­vironmental challenge is highly predictable-once the nature of its autopolesls is understood. Clever politicians intuit those adaptations; and they can be helped by good scientists using system-theoretic models. Stupid politicians do not understand why social institutions do not lose their Identities overnight when they are presented with perfectly logical reasons why they should; and these are helped by bad scientists who devote their effort to developing that irrelevant logic.”

ACKNOWLEDGEMENT

I am grateful to Norbert Pierre for his valuable programming and computational assistance and to George Klir for his continuing encouragement and editorial support. Personal com­munications with Stafford Beer, Heinz von Foerster, Friedrich von Hayek, Erich Jantsch, Gordon Pask, Ricardo Uribe, Hugo Uyttenhove and Francisco Varela were extremely stimulating and influential. This project was  partially supported  through the Faculty Research Grant of the Graduate School of Business at Columbia University.

REFERENCES

  1. G. Varela, H. R. Maturana and R. B. Uribe, “Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems, its characterization and a model.” Biosystems, 5, 4, 1974, 187-196.
  2. Trentowski, StosuneK filozofii do Cybernetyki czyli sztuki rzadzenia narodom. J. K. Zupanski, Poznan, 1843.
  3. A. Bogdanov, Tekto/ogiia: vseobschaia organizatsion­ naia nauka. Z. I. Grschebin Verlag, Berlin, 1922.
  4. Leduc, The Mechanism of Life. Rebman Ltd., London, 1911.
  5. Ch. Smuts, Ho/ism and Evolution. Greenwood Press, Westport, Conn., 1973.
  6. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1973.
  7. R. Maturana, “The Organization of the Living: a  Theory of the Living Organization.” International Journal of Man-Machine Studies, 7, 1975, 313-332.
  8. G. Varela, “The Arithmetics of Closure,” In: Pro­ceedings of the Third European Meeting on Cybernetics and Systems Research, Vienna, Ap il 1976. To appear.
  9. R. Maturana and F. G. Varela, Autopoietic Systems. Biological Computer Laboratory, BCL Report No. 9.4, Department of Electrical Engineering, University of Il­ linois, Urbana, Illinois, September 1975.
  10. R. Maturana and F. G. Varela, De Maquinas y Seros Vivos. Editorial Universitaria, Santiago, Chile, 1973.
  11. von Foerster, An Epistemology for Living Things. Biological Computer Laboratory, BCL Report No. 9.3, Department of Electrical Engineering, University of Il­ linois, Urbana, Illinois, 1972.
  12. R. Maturana, “Neurophysiology of Cognition.” In: Cognition: A Multiple View. Edited by P. Garvin, Spartan Books, New York, 1970, 3-23.
  13. Zeleny, “APL-AUTOPOIESIS: Experiments in Self­ Organization of Complexity.” In: Proceedings  of  the Third European Meeting on Cybernetics and Systems Research, Vienna, April, 1976. To appear.
  14. von Foerster, “Computing in the Semantic Domain.” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 184, June 1971, 239-241.
  15. Zeleny and N. A. Pierre, “Simulation Models of Autopoietic Systems.” In: Proceedings of the 1975 Sum­ mer Computer Simulation Conference, Simulations Council, La Jolla, California, 1975, 831-842.
  16. Zeleny and N. A. Pierre, “Simulation of Self-renewing Systems.” In:  Evolution  and  ConsciousnessEdited by Jantsch and C. H. Waddington, Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass., 1976.
  17. P. Jackson, Jr., Introduction to Artificial Intelligence,Petrocelli Books, New York, 1974.
  18. M. Elgen, “Self-Organization of Matter and the Organiza­tion of Biological Macromolecules .” Natur­ wissenschaften, 10, 1971,
  19. G. Pask, Conversation, Cognition and Learning. Elsevier, New York,
  20. G. Spencer-Brown, Laws of Form. The Julian Press, New York, 1972.
  21. F. Hayek, Kinds of Order in Society . Studies in Social Theory, No. 5, Institute for Humane Studies, Menlo Park, Califo rnia, 1975.
  22. G. Varela, “A Calculus for Self-Reference.” Interna­ tional Journal of General Systems, 2, 5, 1975. 
  23. H. Pattee, “Physical Problems of the Origin of Natural Controls.” In: Biogenesis-Evolution-Homeostasis. Edited by A. Locker, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1973, 41-49.
  24. G. Pask, “Minds and Media in Education and Entertain­ment: Some Theoretical Comments Illustrated by the Design and Operation of a System for Exteriorising and Manipulating Individual Theses.” Proceedings of the Third European Meeting on Cybernetics and Systems Research , Vienna, April 1976. To
  25. Pask, Conversation Theory: Applications in Education and Epistemology . Elsevier, New York, 1976.
  26. G. Pask, “Interaction Between Individuals, Its Stability and Style.” Mathematical  Biosciences, 11,  1971, 59-84.
  27. K. Rome and S. C. Rome, Organizational Growth Through Decision-Making. American Elsevier, New York, 1971.
  28. H. von Foerster , “Molecular Ethology.” In: Molecular Mechanisms of Memory and Learning. Edited by C. Ungar, Plenum Press, New York,
  29. Beer, ” Preface of Autopoietic Systems. ” In: H. R. Maturana, F. G. Varela, Autopoietic Systems, BCL Report No. 9.4, University of Illinois , Urbana, Ill., 1975, 1-16.
  30. Janisch, Design for Evolution, George Braziller, New York, 1975.
  31. Beer and J. Casti, “Investment Against Disaster in Large Organizations .” NASA Research Memorandum, RM-75-16, April 1975.
  32. Beer, Platform for Change. John Wiley & Sons, New York, 1975. ·
  33. Menger, Untersuchungen uber die methode der Sozialwissenschaften und der Politischen Okonomie in­ sbesondere, Duncker & Humblot, Leipzig, 1883.
  34. Locker,  “Systemogenesis as a Paradigm or Biogenesis.” In: Biogenesis-EvolutionHomeostasis. Edited by A. Locker,  Springer-Verlag,  New  York,  1973, 1-7.
  35. Gierer, “Hydra as a Model for the Development of Biological Form.” Scientific American , December 1974, 44-54.
  36. Gardner, “On Cellular Automata, Self-reproduction. The Garden of Eden, and the Game of Life.” Scientific American, 224, 2, 1971.

About  the  Authors

HUMBERTO R. MATURANA

marturanaHumberto R. Maturana was born in Santiago, Chile in 1928. He studied medicine in Chile and then anatomy at the University College in London under J.Z. Young. Dr. Maturana’s research interests have been in neuroanatomy and neurophysiology. At M.I.T., in cooperation with Lettvin,  McCulloch and Pitts, he was involved in experimental work on neurophysiology of perception in the frog’s eye, explor­ing the functional relationship between the perceptual sorting in the retina and the anatomy of the retinal cells. While teaching biology at the Medical School in San­tiago, he developed the theory of the closed organiza­tion of living systems. This was first formulated as the theory of “autopoiesis” in collaboration with Francisco Varela in 1973. Professor Maturana’s recent concerns are mostly with problems of cognition. Address: Facultad de Ciencias, Department de Biologia, Univer­ sidad de Chile, Casilla 653, Santiago, Chile.

RICARDO B. URIBE

uribeRicardo 8. Uribe was born in Santiago, Chile in 1935. He received  both  B.S. (1957) and M.S. (1960) from the University of Chile. During 1960-1977 he held various appointments in the Department of Electrical Engineering in the School of Engineering of the University of Chile. He also served as an Associate Professor at the Catholic University of Chile (1971-1972). Currently, he is associated with the Department of Electrical Engineer­ ing at the University of Illinois and with the Department of Cybernetics at Brunel University in London. His in­ terests are centered around the study and development of organizationally closed systems (and the organiza­tions that may evolve from their interactions) as well as the tools, like networks of microprocessors, that may lead to their realization. Address: University of Illinois, 155 Electrical Engineering Building,  Urbana, Illinois 61801.

FRANCISCO  J. VARELA

varelaFrancisco J. Varela was born in Chile in 1946. He studied biology with Humberto Maturana at the Universidad de Chile in Santiago. Later he received a Ph.D. in Biology from Harvard University, in 1970. His main interests lie in what McCulloch called “ex­perimental  epistemology,” that is, the natural history and possible mechanisms of knowing. F.J. Varela published many papers in the areas of cybernetics, neurobiology, and philosophy of science. In addition to writing the original  monograph on autopoiesis, co-authored with H.R. Maturana, he also  published  Principles of Biological Autonomy, in 1979. Currently he serves as an Associate Professor of Biology at the University of Chile. Address: Facultad de Ciencias, Universidad de Chile, Casilla 653, Santiago, Chile.

MILAN ZELENY

zelenyMilan Zeleny was born in Prague in 1942. He received an Ing. degree from Prague School of   Economics, and M.S. and Ph.D. degrees from the University of  Rochester. Dr. Zeleny published over 100 papers and articles  on topics of multiple criteria decision making, mathematical programming, computer simulation, autopoietic systems, game theory, economics, the theory of risk, critical path analysis, and judgmental psychology. Among his many books are for example, Linear Multiobjective Programming, Multiple Criteria Decision Making, Uncertain Prospects Ranking and Portfolio Analysis,Towards a Self-Service Society, and Autopoiesis, Dissipative Structures and Spontaneous Social Orders. He serves on editorial boards of Com­puters and Operations Research, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, General Systems Yearbook, and Human Systems Management. He is currently Professor at Fordham University in New York. Address: The  Joseph Martino Graduate School of Business Administration, Fordham University at Lincoln Center, New York, N.Y. 10023.

Leave a Reply

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.